Philosophy 5550
Seminar 1 - Skepticism - Part 2
Michael Huemer on Skepticism – Continued
Chapter III of Skepticism and the Veil of Perception: “Easy Answers to Skepticism”
1. Is Skepticism Self-Refuting?
1. Mike Huemer points out that regardless of what may be
the case with regard to radical, universal skepticism, skepticism about
the external world is not self-refuting.
2. He then goes on to argue that radical, universal skepticism is
self-refuting, not because it is self-contradictory, but because “its
truth would entail our lack of justification for asserting it.”
(28)
3. The gist of Mike Huemer's argument is that the universal
skeptic will not be able to claim either that his or her premises are
justified, or that, given those premises, the conclusion is justified.
4. A crucial point is that the universal skeptic cannot even
advance a reductio ad absurdum argument, since this presupposes that
deductive reasoning is a justified method of arriving at beliefs.
Comment
I think that Mike Huemer is right about radical, universal skepticism.
**************************************************************************
5. One conclusion that Mike Huemer wants to draw is that the
first two skeptical arguments considered in the previous chapter are
self-refuting, since they are defenses of universal skepticism.
Comments
(1) Those two arguments can be recast, however, so that they are
defenses not of radical, universal skepticism, but of skepticism with
regard to the external world.
(2) This can be done, in the case of the infinite regress argument, by
holding that some propositions expressing necessary truths can be
non-inferentially justified.
(3) Similarly, in the case of the "problem of the criterion" argument,
one can hold, first, that self-contradictory propositions are
necessarily false, and, secondly, that the form of a proposition is
something that one can directly recognize.
(4) Moreover, there is a form of skepticism that is more modest, but
still extremely threatening: it is what might be referred to as
universal skepticism about the justification of beliefs involving all
contingent propositions. This view seems to me clearly not
self-refuting, since this thesis, if true, is a necessary truth, not a
contingent one, and the skeptic can use arguments that involve only
necessary truths to attempt to prove that there is not contingent
proposition that one can ever be justified in believing.
2. The G. E. Moore Shift
G. E. Moore's Formulation of his Argument
In his essay “Hume's Theory Examined,” G. E. Moore discusses an
argument for external world skepticism that is based upon what he
refers to as “Hume's principles", and he offers the following argument
against Hume's principles:
“It seems to me that, in fact, there really is no stronger and better
argument than the following. I do know that this pencil exists; but I
could not know this, if Hume's principles were true; therefore, Hume's
principles, one or both of them, are false. I think that this argument
really is as strong and good a one as any that could be used: and I
think that it really is conclusive In other words, I think that the
fact that if Hume's principles were true, I could not know of the
existence of this pencil, is a reduction ad absurdum of those
principles.”
(HTE, pp. 119-20)
Moore then goes on, first of all, to argue that one could not have any
knowledge at all unless there were some propositions of whose truth one
had immediate (or non-inferential) knowledge, and then he claims that
among the immediate knowledge that it is possible to have is, for
example, knowledge that one is presently holding and seeing is a pencil.
But is it true that one can have immediate knowledge of the existence
of physical objects? This might after all be challenged by an argument
claiming that immediate knowledge is restricted to propositions about
things of which one can be directly aware, and it might be claimed that
one can only be directly aware of the contents of one's own mental
states.
One way of responding to this objection is by holding that one can be
directly aware of physical states of affairs, and as we shall see when
we turn to chapter IV of Mike Huemer's Skepticism and the Veil of Perception
– “A Version of Direct Realism” – Mike Huemer holds that one can be
directly aware of physical states of affairs. But G. E. Moore
does not, so that type of reply is not available to him. His
response is instead as follows:
“But whether the exact proposition which formed my premise, namely: I
do know that this pencil exists; or only the proposition: This pencil
exists; or only the proposition: The sense data which I directly
apprehend are a sign that it exists; is known by me immediately, one or
the other of them, I think, certainly is so. And all three of them are
much more certain than any premiss which could be used to prove that
they are false; and also much more certain than any other premiss which
could be used to prove that they are true. That is why I say that the
strongest argument to prove that Hume's principles are false is the
argument from a particular case, like this in which we know of the
existence of some material object. (HTE, pp. 125-6)
Huemer's Defense of the G. E. Moore's Argument
Mike Huemer discussion of the Moorean defense against skepticism is as follows.
1. Mike Huemer points out that G. E. Moore actually responds to Hume's
argument for skepticism – in “Hume's Theory Examined” (in Some Main Problems of Philosophy).
2. Mike Huemer's goal in this section is to set out an argument
to show that skeptical arguments cannot succeed against common sense
beliefs.
3. Earlier, common sense beliefs were defined as follows:
"i. They are accepted by almost everyone
(except some philosophers and some madmen) regardless of what culture
or time period one belongs to.
ii. They tend to be taken for granted in ordinary life . . ..
iii. If a person believes a contrary to one of
these propositions, then it is a sign of insanity." (18)
Comments
(1) It is very important to notice that Mike Huemer's definition of
common sense beliefs is not a definition of what it is to be a common
sense belief at some specific time t. Thus he does not say, for
example, that for the belief that p to be a common sense belief at time
t, p must have been accepted by almost everyone at every time up to and
including time t. What he defines is a non-temporally-indexed
concept of “common sense belief", according to which to be a common
sense belief, p must be accepted by almost everyone at every time,
past, present, and future.
(2) To know (or be justified in believing), then, for example, that the
belief that there are rocks is a common sense belief, one must know (or
be justified in believing) that the belief that there are rocks will be
accepted by almost everyone in the future.
(3) The fact that the belief that p has been accepted by almost
everyone at every time up to and including time t does not therefore
entail that p is a common sense belief. Does knowing that p has
been accepted by almost everyone at every time up to and including time
t justify one in believing, at time t, that p is a common sense
belief? If not, what more is required?
(4) Suppose that p has been accepted by almost everyone at every time
up to and including time t, and will, as things turn out, also be
accepted by almost everyone at every time in the future, whereas while
q has been accepted by almost everyone at every time up to and
including time t, it will not, as a matter of future fact, be accepted
by almost everyone at every time in the future. Is it necessarily
the case that there must be something that enables one to be justified
in believing, at time t, that p will be accepted by everyone in the
future, whereas q will not be? If so, what would that be?
(5) The underlying questions, in short, are these:
(a) First of all, among the beliefs that have been accepted by almost
everyone at every time up to and including the present moment, can one
tell which of those are common sense beliefs and which are not, and
thus, which of those beliefs have the highest level of initial
plausibility, and which do not?
(b) If one can tell, how can one do this? How can one distinguish
between those beliefs that will be accepted by almost everyone at all
future times, and those that will not?
**************************************************************************
4. The defense against skepticism that Mike offers here involves the following argument:
"1. Given a conflict between two beliefs, it is rational to
reject the less initially plausible one, rather than the more plausible
one.
2. Common sense beliefs have the highest level of initial plausibility.
3. Philosophical theories do not.
4. Therefore, given a conflict between a philosophical theory and
common sense, it is rational to reject the philosophical theory, rather
than common sense."
(SVP, p. 36)
5. In support of the second premise, that is
Common sense beliefs have the highest level of initial plausibility.
Mike argues as follows,
“But the nature of common sense beliefs, as such, is that they have the
highest initial plausibility of all beliefs. This, in fact, may serve
as a useful definition of common sense beliefs; it explains the other
features of common sense beliefs that we noted in section II.5. Common
sense beliefs are almost universally accepted, regardless of time and
place, because they are the most obvious propositions.” (SVP, p.
33)
Mike also argues that while massive scientific
testimony could convince one that something like the Theorem of
Pythagoras was false, it would not convince one, for example, that
there were no rocks.
Question: Is it true that all common sense beliefs have the highest level of initial plausibility?
(1) It is not true that all common sense beliefs have the highest level
of initial plausibility, since some common sense beliefs have a higher
level of initial plausibility than others. For example, my common
sense belief that I am now having experiences has a higher initial
plausibility for me than my common sense belief that I am now seeing a
desk. Moreover, my treating the former belief as initially more
plausible than the latter is surely justified, since the truth of the
latter belief entails the truth of the former, but not vice versa.
(2) Similarly, the common sense belief that there are other human
bodies should have a higher initial plausibility for one than the
common sense belief that there are other human bodies that have minds
that enjoy experiences.
(3) Scientific testimony has convinced people that some beliefs that
were common sense beliefs – in the ordinary, temporally indexed, sense
of “common sense beliefs” – are false. Thus it was once a common
sense belief that a quality with which normal perceivers are directly
acquainted – namely, the occurrent, sensible property of redness – was
a quality out there on the surfaces of objects such as ripe
tomatoes. If physics is right, there is no reason for believing
that there is any such property on the surfaces of ripe tomatoes.
(4) Other common sense beliefs – in the ordinary, temporally-indexed,
sense of “common sense beliefs” – that science has given us good reason
for abandoning include, for example, the following beliefs:
(a) The belief that when one touches an orange, the matter in one's hand comes in contact with the matter in the orange;
(b) The belief that most of the space occupied by a coin is occupied by matter in the coin, rather than by empty space.
(5) So it can be rational in some cases to abandon common sense
beliefs, in the ordinary sense of “common sense beliefs.”
****************************************************************************
6. In support of the third premise, that is
Philosophical theories do not have the highest level of initial plausibility.
Mike argues that the disagreement over philosophical claims shows that
they do not have the highest level of initial plausibility.
Comments
(1) Mike Huemer refers here to philosophical theories.
(2) It is true that philosophical theories do not generally elicit a
high level of agreement, and it is fair to say that that shows that
philosophical theories do not possess the highest level of initial
plausibility.
(3) On the other hand, there can be philosophical claims that do not
involve philosophical theories in an ordinary sense, and that may have
either very high initial plausibility, or else very high plausibility
upon further reflection and argument, so one needs to consider the
possibility of a collision between such philosophical claims and common
sense beliefs.
****************************************************************************
Mike Huemer advances the following claim: “No skeptic has ever devised
an argument whose premises were not more controversial than the common
sense beliefs the skeptic seeks to challenge.” (SVP, p. 36) I
shall now argue that this can be done.
3. A First General Point: Philosophical Theories Versus Philosophical Claims
1. Consider the following claims:
(a) Reality consists of nothing except God plus finite immaterial minds and their mental states.
(b) Berkeley's theory is not significantly more complex than the theory that there are mind-independent external objects.
(c) The observational predictions of Berkeley's theory are the same as
the predictions of the theory that there are mind-independent objects.
(d) If two theories S and T generate the same observational
predictions, and theory S is only slightly more complex than T, then
the ratio of the a priori logical probability of S to that of the a priori logical probability of T will be only slightly different from one.
(e) The a priori logical probability of Berkeley's theory is not significantly lower than the a priori logical probability of the theory that there are mind-independent objects.
(f) Bayes' Theorem is true. (Or: The definition of conditional probability is consistent.)
Only the first of these would naturally be characterized as a
philosophical theory. At the same time, the other five claims are
very relevant to the question of the epistemic status of the first.
2. To see this, let us introduce the following abbreviations:
p = The proposition that there is a specific world, W, involving mind-independent objects.
m = The proposition that there is instead an exactly corresponding
Berkeleyan world – that is, a Berkeleyan world in which precisely the
same experiences will exist as would exist if p were true.
e = A proposition concerning the totality of the sensory experiences that will exist if p is true.
So e is a proposition that is entailed both by p and by m.
Prob(q) = the a priori logical (or epistemic) probability that q is the case.
Prob(q, r) = the logical (or epistemic) probability that q is the case given that r is the case.
If claims (b), (c), and (d) above are correct, or at least near enough, then it is the case that
(1) If Prob(m)/Prob(p) is less than one, it is only slightly less than one.
But by the definition of conditional probability, which is
Prob(m/e) = Prob(m & e), one has that
Prob(e)
(2) Prob(m/e) x Prob(e) = Prob(m & e) = Prob(e/m) x Prob(m)
and, similarly, that
(3) Prob(p/e) x Prob(e) = Prob(p & e) = Prob(e/p) x Prob(p)
Moreover, in view of the fact that p entails e, we have that
(4) Prob(e/p) = 1
Similarly, in view of the fact that m also entails e, we also have that
(5) Prob(e/m) = 1
Substituting 5 and 4 into 2 and 3 then gives us, respectively:
(6) Prob(m/e) x Prob(e) = Prob(m)
and
(7) Prob(p/e) x Prob(e) = Prob(p)
Dividing equation 6 by equation 7 then yields
(8) Prob(m/e)/Prob(p/e) = Prob(m)/Prob(p)
But this means, in view of its being the case that if Prob(m)/Prob(p) is less than one, it is only slightly less than one, that
(9) Prob(m/e)/Prob(p/e) is only slightly less than one.
In short, the a posteriori logical
probability that Berkeley's view of reality is correct, relative to the
totality of experiences that one has, is either equal to, or else only
slightly less than, the a posteriori logical probability that there is a world of mind-independent physical objects.
3. Notice the following important contrast. If Berkeley's view of
the world is true, that is a contingent truth. In contrast,
claims (b) through (f), if true, are necessary truths.
4. This is very important. For necessary truths can have an
initial plausibility that is greater than that of a contingent common
sense belief such as that there are rocks. In addition, even in
the case of necessary truths whose initial plausibility is not
especially high, investigation can show that the proposition in
question is not only extremely plausible, but also more plausible than
contingent common sense beliefs concerning the external world.
5. To sum up, then, it is a mistake to think that the only way of
challenging a common sense belief is by opposing it by a philosophical
theory. One can instead appeal to philosophical claims that do
not involve advancing any philosophical theories, and argue that those
claims lead to the conclusion that a certain common sense belief does
not have the probability that is being assigned to it. Moreover,
the philosophical claims in question may be necessary truths, and they
can have either an initial plausibility that is higher than that of
contingent common sense beliefs about the external world, or else a
plausibility upon subsequent reflection that is higher than that of
contingent common sense beliefs about the external world.
The way of challenging common sense beliefs that I have just
described involves what might be called “purely philosophical
arguments.” But, as we shall see in the next section, there can
also be philosophical arguments against common sense beliefs that make
use of well-established scientific claims. One then needs to
argue that the scientific claim in question can achieve a level of
plausibility that is greater than that of the common sense belief that
it is being used against. I shall not attempt to show that here,
but I think that the claim is very plausible.
4. A Second General Point: Inferential Versus Non-Inferential Beliefs
1. The vast majority of common sense beliefs are inferential
beliefs. Thus, for example, in the case of beliefs about
presently existing, but not currently perceived objects, all such
beliefs rest upon everyday conservation principles.
2. Even if one confines oneself to beliefs about currently perceived
objects, those beliefs typically go beyond what one is directly
acquainted with, in the following ways:
(a) One believes that the things one sees are not facades.
(b) One believes that the things one sees have insides of a certain sort.
(c) One believes that the things one sees have tactile qualities.
(d) One believes that other observers would also see the things one sees if they were present.
(e) One believes that the things one sees would exist even if one were not seeing them.
3. When beliefs are inferential, the fact that their plausibility is
not substantially reduced by certain sorts of challenges is compatible
with its being the case that challenges specifically directed against
the underlying inferences may radically reduce their plausibility.
4. When a common sense belief is inferential, it is apparent that the
plausibility of that belief is a function of the plausibility of the
inference involved, and it may then very well be the case that,
confronted with a competing inference, leading to an incompatible
conclusion, one’s estimate of the plausibility of the original
inference – and so also of the original belief – plummets.
5. Suppose, in particular, that the following things turned out to be true:
(a) One's beliefs about external objects that one is currently perceiving are inferential beliefs.
(b) The inference is an inference to the best explanation.
(c) Berkeley's theory does not differ much from the theory of physical objects with regard to simplicity.
Then it would seem that the plausibility of the theory that there is a
spacetime world containing mind-independent physical objects should
drop very significantly.
5. Some Specific Cases to Consider: Candidate Common Sense Beliefs
If the G. E. Moore/Michael Huemer anti-skepticism argument is sound,
then it is always rational, given a conflict between a philosophical
theory and a common sense belief, to reject the philosophical theory,
rather than the common sense belief. Is this true?
To see whether this is right, let's consider some beliefs that either
are or were common sense beliefs, in the ordinary, temporally indexed
sense of that expression, along with some incompatible philosophical
theories.
Comments
(1) If one talks, as I just did, about beliefs that either now are or
were common sense beliefs, one is operating with a temporally indexed
interpretation of the expression “common sense beliefs".
(2) I think that this is our ordinary interpretation of that expression.
(3) If one adopted, instead, Mike's interpretation of that expression,
one would need to rephrase things in terms of “beliefs that either are
or were candidates for common sense beliefs.”
(4) The issue that arises, in view of the option here, is whether G. E.
Moore and/or Mike Huemer have an anti-skepticism argument that applies
to common sense beliefs in Mike’s sense of that expression, but not to
common sense beliefs in the temporally-indexed sense.
(5) For that to be the case, one would have to be able to show that
while beliefs that are common sense beliefs in Mike's sense have the
highest initial plausibility at a given time, beliefs that are common
sense beliefs only in the temporally-indexed sense at that time do not
have the highest initial plausibility at that time. I do not
think that there is any reason for thinking that that is so in general.
**************************************************************************
In any case, here are some beliefs that either are, or were, common
sense beliefs in the temporally indexed sense of that expression.
(1) The belief that a certain ripe tomato is red, where this is
understood as the belief that a young child would have about the color
property of the surface of a ripe tomato.
Competing philosophical theory: Physics is a complete theory of the external world.
(2) The belief that there are mind-independent physical objects.
Competing philosophical theory: Idealism.
(3) The belief that human behavior is not causally determined.
Competing philosophical theory: Determinism.
(4) The belief that humans possess libertarian free will
Competing philosophical theories: (a) Determinism; (b) The view
that libertarian free will is incoherent; (c) The view that to the
extent that human behavior is not causally determined, what one does is
simply a matter of indeterministic quantum processes: there is nothing
else that is causally relevant.
(5) The belief that non-human mammals have experiences.
Competing philosophical theory: Animals have only properties that
are reducible to those of physics. (Compare Descartes.)
(6) The belief that decisions to perform actions are not caused by earlier, purely physical events in the brain.
Competing philosophical theory: Decisions are caused by earlier,
purely physical events in the brain. (Consider Benjamin Libet's
experiment.)
(7) The belief that one's experiences can causally make a difference with regard to the way that one's body moves.
Competing philosophical theory: Epiphenomenalism.
(8) The belief that there are objective facts concerning the rightness
and wrongness of actions, or the goodness and badness of states of
affairs, and that we can have knowledge of such objective values.
Competing philosophical theories: (a) Moral irrealism and (b) Moral skepticism.
With regard to each of the above pairs of a suggested common sense
belief, and a competing and incompatible philosophical theory, there
are four questions that one needs to ask:
First, are the theories that I have just
characterized as "competing philosophical theories" philosophical
theories?
Secondly, is the belief in question a common sense belief in Mike's sense?
Thirdly, if it is, is Mike right in holding that it
is impossible for there to be an argument that would give us good
reason to reject the common sense belief in favor of the competing
philosophical theory?
Fourthly, if the belief in question is not a common
sense belief in Mike's sense, was it at one time a common sense belief
in the ordinary, temporally-indexed sense of “common sense belief"?
The point of the fourth question was, in effect,
described earlier. It is that if a belief is a common sense
belief in the ordinary, temporally-indexed sense of that expression,
but is not a common sense belief in Mike's sense – because, say, it is
now widely rejected – then Mike has the task of either (1) showing that
the belief in question did not possess, at the relevant time, the same
high level of initial plausibility as beliefs that are common sense
beliefs in his sense of that expression, or (2) of explaining how
people could ever be justified in rejecting the beliefs in question if
those beliefs had as high a level of initial plausibility at that time
as beliefs that are common sense beliefs in Mike's sense.
As regards the first question, it certainly seems to me that what I
have labeled "competing philosophical theories" are indeed such.
Does anyone think that in some of the above cases this is not so?
The other questions call for more discussion, so let's consider each candidate in turn.
Candidate 1: Colors, as a child would understand them, are real, and are properties of the surfaces of objects.
Competing philosophical theory: Physics is a complete theory of the external world.
1. What are young children saying when they say that a tomato is red? One thing that they are clearly not saying is this:
(1) “Ripe tomatoes have the power to absorb the following wavelengths
of light . . . and the power to reflect the following wavelengths of
light . . .”
But it also seems clear that they are also not saying this:
(2) “Ripe tomatoes have the power to produce experiences in normal
observers under normal conditions that have the property of qualitative
redness.”
For while it may be argued that arriving at the belief that is
expressed by sentence (2) does not, in contrast to what is so in the
case of sentence (1), require specialized scientific knowledge, the
belief in question is not the belief that people naturally
acquire. The belief that people naturally acquire involves the
concept of a sensible property of redness – where by this I mean the
property that Mary in Frank Jackson's “knowledge argument” is aware of
when she learns what redness is. When a child says that a tomato
is red, it is this sensible, non-dispositional property that is being
attributed to the surface of the tomato. Redness is a property
with which a child is directly acquainted, and in such a way that the
child, like Mary, knows what redness is. It is not, as David
Armstrong, for example, contends, some property about whose intrinsic
nature one initially knows nothing.
In short, there is a certain property with which a child is directly
acquainted – the property of redness – and a child, in believing that a
ripe tomato is red, believes that that the surface of the tomato has
that property.
Is this a common sense belief? One might object that it is not,
on the grounds that one does not now have to be a philosopher or a
madman to reject it. But this defense seems unsound to me.
For suppose that one goes back a few hundred years, and ignores certain
parts of Asia. It would surely have been reasonable then to have
viewed the belief in question as a common sense belief in the
temporally indexed sense of that expression. But would it not
also be true, at that time, that that belief would have had just as
high a level of initial plausibility as beliefs that Mike would view as
common sense beliefs – such as the belief that other humans have
minds? But if that is right, then, if Mike Huemer's argument were
sound, it would have been reasonable at that time to continue to accept
that common sense belief when it came into conflict with a
philosophical argument, as it did. But, in fact, those who are
familiar with the relevant scientific information have almost
universally come to hold that ripe tomatoes do not have the sensible,
non-dispositional property of redness.
The upshot is that the belief that things are colored in the relevant
sense was once a common sense belief, but it has been abandoned by
almost everyone who is familiar with the relevant scientific
facts. So some common sense beliefs ¬ in the ordinary sense of
“common sense belief” – have succumbed to philosophical arguments based
on well-established scientific premises.
Candidate 2: There are mind-independent physical objects.
Competing philosophical theory: Idealism.
Is this a common sense belief, in Mike's sense? My argument for
the claim that, contrary to Mike's view, it is not, is as follows:
(1) Hinduism, which is the religion of over 600 million people,
involves the idea of maya, where this is the view that there is no
physical world, that what one has is, instead, an illusion.
(2) A significant number of Hindus affirm this belief, and there is
nothing in their behavior that provides a reason for thinking that they
are wrong in this self-attribution.
(3) These people are not all either philosophers or mad.
(4) Accordingly, the belief that there are mind-independent physical objects is not a common sense belief in Mike's sense.
Mike's response to this argument was that he found it hard to believe
that people really believed the doctrine of maya. His ground, I
think, involved the claims, first, that Hindus do not act in the way
that they would if they believed that the physical world is an
illusion, and, secondly, that the way that one acts can show that one
is mistaken in attributing a certain belief to oneself.
But if that is Mike's ground, the objection is that a Berkeleian does
not, on the whole, have reasons for acting differently than a person
who believes in a physical world. So, for example, if Berkeley is
right about the nature of reality, and one has the experience as of
putting one's hand in a fire, one's pain will be just as great as it
would be if there were a physical world.
Consequently, I don't think that there is any very good ground for
being skeptical about the correctness of a Hindu who claims to believe
that the physical world is an illusion.
Now it is true, it seems to me, and as Thomas Reid pointed out, that if
Berkeley's theory is true, then one does not have a good reason for
believing in the existence of other human minds. But given that
very few people – including Berkeley – have noticed this fact about
Berkeley's theory, I do not think that this fact is good grounds for
concluding that Hindus do not have the belief that they take themselves
to have – that is, the belief that the physical world is an illusion.
In addition, however, compare the following beliefs:
(a) There is a perfectly loving, all powerful, and all knowing being who created and who rules over our world.
(b) There is some being who has produced a grand illusion that people experience, to the effect that there is a physical world.
The first of these propositions seems to me much more likely to be
false, given the immense suffering that both innocent persons –
including children – and animals undergo, than the second. But
the first proposition is nevertheless affirmed by an extremely large
number of people. So why should one accept Mike's view that
Hindus do not really accept the second belief?
Furthermore, religious beliefs often come as a package deal, with the
result that people accept beliefs that are immensely implausible
– such as the belief that the earth is only a few thousand years old,
which is still accepted by more than 40% of our fellow Americans –
because they view those beliefs as an essential part of a total view of
the world that they find appealing. So even if it were true that
there would be no grounds for behaving as one does if one believed that
the physical world was not real, that would not provide a good reason
for concluding that Hindus do accept the doctrine of maya.
Finally, there is a type of experience that is found in all, or
virtually all, cultures – what are known as introvertive mystical
experiences. Moreover, in the description of such experiences
that is, arguably, most free of the importation of prior beliefs –
namely, the monistic account offered in Eastern religions, as
contrasted with the monotheistic account offered by Christian mystics –
a central aspect of the experience is the sense that the world of space
and time is not real. The Hindu doctrine of maya is largely
based, I believe, on such introvertive mystical experiences.
The second issue is this. If, contrary to what I have just
argued, the belief that there is a world of mind-independent physical
objects were a common sense belief in Mike's sense, could it be
defended against skeptical challenges by Mike's argument?
Mike's argument appeals to the idea that common sense beliefs are
characterized by the "highest level of initial
plausibility". But judgments of plausibility are judgments
of probability. How reliable are ordinary judgments of
probability?
Some judgments of probability are based upon observations of relative
frequencies, and such judgments may be relatively sound. But in
the present case, there is no information about relative frequencies
that bears upon the issue. So what we are being asked by Mike to
do is to view, as very reliable, judgments of probability, first of
all, that are not based upon relative frequencies; secondly, that are
being made by people without serious consideration of competing
hypotheses – such as the mystically-based doctrine of maya; and,
thirdly, that are judgments that Mike himself is unable to support by
appealing to principles of probability or inductive logic.
Candidate 3: The belief that human behavior is not causally determined.
Competing philosophical theory: Determinism.
Is the belief that human behavior is not causally determined a common
sense belief? I think that it is, since I think that it is
natural to think that, at any given time, one could, for example,
either move one's hand to the right, or move it to the left.
Moreover, one does not, initially, seem to have any reason at all for
thinking that, on the contrary, what one does is in fact causally
determined.
Is it then true that science could no more convince one that this
belief was false than it could convince one that there were no rocks?
This does not seem right. For couldn't it have been the case that
the correct theory of physics was Newtonian, and so
deterministic? ? Or mightn't the indeterministic
interpretation of quantum physics that is presently accepted by most
physicists come to be replaced by the deterministic alternative?
Or mightn't present, indeterministic theories in quantum mechanics be
replaced at some point by a deterministic theory?
It might be objected that what physicists would have shown, in such
cases, would be only that determinism held with regard to inanimate
objects. But couldn't the work of physicists be supplemented by
neurophysiological experiments that established that events taking in
place in the brain conformed to the deterministic laws discovered by
physicists? If so, then this third belief would be shown to be
false.
Candidate 4: The belief that humans possess libertarian free will
Competing philosophical theories: (a) Determinism; (b) The idea
of libertarian free will is incoherent; (c) The view that to the extent
that human behavior is not causally determined, what one does is simply
a matter of indeterministic quantum processes: there is nothing else
that is causally relevant.
Is the belief that humans possess libertarian free will a common sense
belief? I think that it is, since it seems to me, as was
mentioned in connection with the previous candidate for a common sense
belief – namely, that human behavior is not causally determined – that
it is natural to think that, at any given time, one could, for example,
either move one's hand to the right, or move it to the left, and that,
moreover, in thinking that one can do either of those things, one is
thinking that one has some sort of power to do either of those things,
a power that is “under one's control.”
It might well be objected, however, that if the claim that is advanced
the second of the two competing philosophical theories just mentioned –
namely, the claim that the idea of libertarian free will is incoherent
– is true, then there is no belief here to be a common sense belief.
I'm inclined to think, however, that one can respond as follows.
First of all, the idea of libertarian free will can be characterized in
a relational, or functional way: libertarian free will is something
whose possession entails that one's actions are not causally
determined, and whose possession is also sufficient to make it the case
that one is causally responsible for one's actions. The claim
that libertarian free will is incoherent is then not the claim that
that functional or relational concept is incoherent, but, rather, the
claim that there is no coherent, intrinsically characterized power or
property answering to that relational or functional description.
Could this belief be overthrown? Since having libertarian free
will is incompatible with its being the case that one's behavior is
causally determined, if the belief that one's behavior is not causally
determined could be overthrown, then so could the belief that one has
libertarian free will.
Candidate 5: The belief that non-human mammals have experiences.
Competing philosophical theory: Animals have only purely physical properties.
Is it a common sense belief that cats and dogs, for example, have experiences? It would certainly seem that it is.
Is it true, then, that a philosophical argument based on scientific
findings could not give one good reason for abandoning this belief in
favor of the Cartesian belief that non-human animals are physical
automata without experiences? It seems to me that it is
not. For imagine that, in the case of human beings,
neurophysiological investigations locate a "visual experience module"
such that, when this is damaged, the human in question, while having a
dramatic type of blindsight, reports having no visual experiences at
all. Suppose that comparable modules are found for all of the
other senses. Suppose, finally, that nothing in the brains of
non-human mammals corresponds to this part of the human brain, and that
all of the structures in all parts of the brains of non-human animals
correspond to structures in human brains that are not sufficient for
the having of experiences. Would not information along these
lines make it reasonable to conclude that while non-human animals
behave as if they had conscious experiences, in fact consciousness only
emerges with the development of certain neuronal structures that are
only present in the human brain, so that Descartes was right, and
non-human mammals do not have experiences of any kind?
Candidate 6: The belief that decisions to perform actions are not caused by earlier, purely physical events in the brain.
Competing philosophical theory: Decisions to act are caused by earlier, purely physical events in the brain.
Is this a common sense belief? Again, I think that it is.
One is aware of conscious processes of considering alternative actions,
and the pros and cons of each. Then, at a certain point, there is
a conscious experience of making a decision, and it seems very natural
to think of that occurrence as one that is not caused by some earlier,
purely physical event.
Some scientists have reported, however, that there are brain events
that take place a very short time before the conscious experience of
making a decision – events that they think it reasonable to view as
causally giving rise to the conscious experience. Thus Benjamin
Libet, in a famous article entitled “Do We Have Free Will?” that was
published in the Journal of Consciousness Studies, 6, No. 8–9, 1999, pp. 47–57, says,
“I have taken an experimental approach to this question. Freely
voluntary acts are preceded by a specific electrical change in the
brain (the ‘readiness potential', RP) that begins 550 ms before the
act. Human subjects became aware of intention to act 350–400 ms after
RP starts, but 200 ms before the motor act. The volitional process is
therefore initiated unconsciously.”
The upshot then, as Michael S. Gazzaniga describes it in chapter 3 of his book The Mind's Past
– entitled "The Brain Knows Before You Do" – is that “. . . before you
are aware that you're thinking about moving your arm, your brain is at
work preparing to make that movement." ( The Mind's Past, (Berkeley and Los Angeles: The University of California Press, 1998), page 73)
But if this is right, is this not a good reason to abandon the common
sense belief in favor of the competing philosophical theory that events
that involve the consciousness of coming to a decision are caused by
earlier, purely physical events?
Candidate 7: The belief that
one’s experiences can causally make a difference with regard to the way
that one's body moves.
Competing philosophical theory: Epiphenomalism.
Is this a common sense belief? It certainly seems to me that it
is. When, for example, one tastes something, and one is asked how
it tastes, surely it is extremely natural to think that the quality of
the experience that one is having plays an essential causal role in
determining the words that one utters in answering the question of how
the thing tastes.
Is it true, then, that an argument for the competing philosophical
theory of epiphenomenalism could not prevail against this common sense
belief? Again, this does not seem right. As with the case
of Candidate 3 above, it would seem that, on the one hand, physicists
could show that determinism held with regard to inanimate objects, and
then cognitive scientists could establish, via extensive
neurophysiological experiments, that events taking in place in the
brain were not exceptions to the deterministic laws discovered by
physicists. If this is so, then the common sense belief that
experiences can make a difference with respect to how humans behave
could be shown to be false.
Candidate 8: The belief that
there are objective facts concerning the rightness and wrongness of
actions, or concerning the goodness and badness of states of affairs,
and that we can have knowledge of such objective values.
Competing philosophical theories: (a) Moral irrealism and (b) Moral skepticism.
Is this a common sense belief? Again, it seems to me very
plausible that it is. For one thing, have anthropologists ever
found a society where people did not have beliefs about the rightness
and wrongness of actions? For another, though many people
question the existence of objective values, it is generally the case
that when certain issues arise, they do not treat those who disagree
with them as simply having different preferences that are no more
problematic than their own. A person who liked to relax by
torturing animals would not generally be viewed as simply having
unusual tastes.
Is it true that this common sense belief is secure, and should prevail
in the face of any challenge from moral irrealism or moral
skepticism? Again, this does not seem to me true. Consider,
for example, the argument from the cultural relativity of values
against the view that there are objective values. The normal
response to this argument is to draw a distinction between basic moral
principles and derived ones, and to argue that the moral disagreements
that one finds between different societies are, on the whole,
disagreements about derived moral principles. This response,
however, is by no means unproblematic, since there seem to be a number
of cases where there is disagreement concerning principles that, at
least for some people, appear to be basic moral principles, sometimes
involving very firm intuitions on both sides. Here are a few
examples:
(1) The enjoyment of sexual pleasure is only morally permissible within
marriage, and when the sexual activity in question is one that is open
to the possibility of conception.
(2) The direct killing of any innocent human being, regardless of his
or her condition, and regardless of whether he or she asks to be
killed, is always seriously wrong.
(3) There are some actions that should never be performed, regardless of the consequences of not performing the action.
(4) The killing of potential persons is morally on a par with the killing of persons.
(5) Killing and letting die are morally on a par.
(6) Suicide is morally wrong, even in cases where one is terminally ill and suffering terribly.
(7) The use of mind-altering drugs is morally wrong.
(8) People who have intentionally killed others when it was wrong to do so should be executed.
(9) We have no obligations with regard to future generations.
(10) Affluent countries have no obligations with regard to people starving to death in other countries.
(11) To each according to his needs.
(12) Goods should be distributed in accordance with desert.
(13) The world is a better world if good and evils are distributed in accordance with desert.
(14) All rights are only negative rights, such a right not to be
killed. There are no positive rights, such as a right to be saved
from death.
(15) If two worlds have the same quantity of goods, but the goods are
differently distributed, the world with the more equal distribution is
the better world, other things being equal.
(16) A world where John suffers on a particular occasion, and is
comforted by someone, is a better world than one where John does not
suffer on the occasion in question.
These disagreements, all of which I think are most likely to be, or to
be very closely related to, disagreements about basic moral principles
– that is, disagreements about rightmaking and wrongmaking, or
goodmaking and badmaking properties – are disagreements about extremely
important issues. Would one expect such disagreements if there
were objective values to which people had cognitive access?
Wouldn't one rather expect that the level of disagreement would be more
on a par with what there is, say, in the case of the colors, or shapes,
of objects?
It seems to me, then, that the argument from relativity poses a strong prima facie challenge to the claim that there are objective moral values to which humans have cognitive access.
There are, in addition, other challenges. One is that it seems
clear that the inculcation of moral values by parents in their children
can produce extremely firm moral opinions and associated moral
feelings, such as guilt and shame that seem unrelated to the truth or
falsity of the belief in question. Consider, for example, the
Biblical views, found in the Old Testament, that women who are not
virgins when they are married should be stoned to death, or that
homosexuals should be put to death, or that people who have sex with
animals should be executed, or that rebellious sons should be
killed. If there are objective values, these particular moral
beliefs are, I would hope, false. But when people who have such
beliefs introspect, carefully and conscientiously, are they able to
detect any difference between those moral beliefs and others that, if
there are moral values, one would hope are true – such as that killing
innocent people is prima facie seriously wrong?
One might compare, here, the case of arithmetic. Imagine parents
who inculcate in their children the belief that Fermat's Last Theorem
is true. Would such children claim to be able to 'see' that
Fermat's Last Theorem is true in just the way that they can see, for
example, that 2 + 2 = 4? Isn't there something phenomenologically
special about one's recognition of simple mathematical truths?
In short, it seems to me that it is not at all clear that the common
sense belief that there are objective values to which one has cognitive
access will not, in the end, turn out to be such as should be abandoned
in the face of relevant philosophical arguments.
6. Concluding Comments on the G. E. Moore/Mike Huemer Argument
(1) It is not true, as Mike Huemer claims, that in a conflict
between common sense views and philosophical theories, common sense
views should always prevail on the grounds that common sense views
"have the highest level of initial plausibility", while competing
philosophical theories do not.
(2) One reason is related to Bertrand Russell's remark, which he made
with regard to color and the manifest image version of naïve realism,
to the effect that the manifest image version of naïve realism leads to
the belief that physics is true, which in turn leads to the conclusion
that the manifest image version of naïve realism is false. The
point, then, is simply that some common sense beliefs involve
observations that serve to support scientific theories that, in the
end, are ultimately very firmly established indeed, and where some of
those scientific theories can then be used by philosophers to argue
that other common sense views are false.
(3) The picture that emerges is that even if common sense views are
often both natural and reasonable initially, they are typically based
upon a very limited range of considerations. Much broader
considerations, often involving much deeper observations, are often
evidentially relevant to common sense beliefs, and, because of this,
philosophical theories that appeal to such considerations can perfectly
well turn out to be more reasonable than the relevant common sense
beliefs with which they conflict.
(4) Finally, there is another way in which one could in principle show
that a common sense belief is not justified, and that does not involve
an appeal to any scientifically established beliefs. It is that
one might be able to use a priori principles
of logical probability to show that a particular common sense belief
was not likely to be true, and therefore not justified.
(5) The clearest illustration of this possibility arises in connection
with skepticism about induction. Thus, consider the following
argument for skepticism concerning non-probabilistic laws of nature:
Laplace's Rule of Succession
If only two outcomes are possible when an event of type E occurs, and
one of those two possible outcomes – say, the occurrence of an event of
type F – has occurred n times, the probability that an event of type F
will occur the next time an event of type E occurs is equal to (n
+ 1)/(n + 2).
As can be shown, it then follows that if only two outcomes are possible
when an event of type E occurs, and one of those two possible outcomes
– the occurrence of an event of type F – has occurred n times,
the probability that an event of type F will occur the next m times an
event of type E occurs is equal to (n+ 1)/(n + m + 1)
Suppose, then, that there is reason to believe that in the history of
the universe, an event of type E will occur an infinite number of
times. The probability that an event of type F will occur every
time is equal to the limit of as m goes to infinity, which
is zero.
Apparent Conclusion
It is impossible to establish that a
non-probabilistic law of nature obtains, since no matter how many times
events of type E have been followed by events of type F, the
probability that that will always be so is zero (or, if one accepts
infinitesimals, infinitesimally close to zero).
(6) Finally, in the case of skepticism concerning the existence of a
mind-independent, physical world, there is the type of argument that I
mentioned earlier:
(a) The idea of there being logical probabilities is a sound one, and so there are numbers that are the a priori logical probabilities of the Berkeleian hypothesis, and of the mind-independent world hypothesis.
(b) The extensive isomorphisms between these two hypotheses, and the
fact that the Berkeleian hypothesis is not significantly more complex
than the mind-independent world hypothesis makes it likely that the
former hypothesis does not have a significantly smaller a priori logical probability than the latter.
(c) These two metaphysical theories make the same predications with regard to all experiences that humans will have.
(d) In view of (c), the logical probability of the occurrence of any
experience, E, should not be any different on Berkeley's hypothesis
from what it is on the mind-independent, physical world hypothesis.
(e) In view of (b) and (d), it follows from Bayes Theorem that the a posteriori probability of the Berkeleian hypothesis will not be significantly smaller than the a posteriori probability of the mind-independent world hypothesis.
(f) Given that this is so, one cannot be justified in assigning a
probability to the mind-independent world hypothesis that is
significantly greater than one half – let alone greater than, say, 0.99.
Concluding Comments
(1) Why do I say “apparent conclusion” above, given that the conclusion
certainly follows from Laplace's Rule of Succession? The reason
is that Laplace's Rule of Succession rests upon unsound equiprobability
assumptions – albeit ones accepted by Laplace, by Thomas Bayes, and by
Rudolf Carnap – and when those unsound equiprobability assumptions are
replaced by sound ones, the conclusion in question no longer follows.
(2) So the above argument for (partial) inductive skepticism is unsound.
(3) The same is true of the above argument for skepticism concerning
the existence of a mind-independent, physical world. The error, I
would argue, is that it is not true that the a priori logical probabilities of the Berkeleian hypothesis, and of the mind-independent world hypothesis, are roughly comparable: the a priori logical probability of the Berkeleian hypothesis is, it turns out, much lower than the a priori logical probability of the mind-independent world hypothesis.
(4) The overall conclusion is that the way to refute skepticism is not
by anything like a G. E. Moore Shift type of argument. What one must do
is to bring the idea of logical probability to bear upon the issue, and
to show that the a priori probability of the skeptical hypothesis that one is considering is much lower than the a priori probability of the non-skeptical alternative.
3. Stroud's Defense
In this section, Mike Huemer considers an objection
to the G. E. Moore Shift Argument advanced by Barry Stroud. Mikes basic
line of argument involves, as I see it, supplementing the line of
argument that he set out earlier with the claim that there are
epistemological views that are alternatives to skepticism that enable
one to preserve one's common sense beliefs.
The relation between what Mike is arguing in this
section and the argument that he set out earlier, on page 36, is not as
clear as it might be. One way of viewing it is as follows.
Someone might claim that the skeptic's epistemological principles can
be seen, upon reflection, to be necessary truths. (It is not clear
whether Barry Stroud is claiming this or not.) But if they are
necessary truths, then they can have a higher level of plausibility –
not necessarily initial plausibility, but plausibility upon reflection
– than common sense beliefs. The idea is then that initial plausibility
does not carry the day, since if reflection leads to any change in
plausibility, it is the resulting plausibilities that are relevant.
If this is right, then what Huemer is doing is
arguing that reflection upon the skeptic's epistemological principles
does not lead to the conclusion that they have a resulting probability
that is greater than that of common sense beliefs, and that it does not
do so because there are alternative epistemological principle that are
not clearly mistaken.
Here is the concluding paragraph of Mike Huemer's discussion in this section:
“ I think that Stroud would accept that, when such a
theory is put forward, it becomes the basis of a legitimate objection
to the skeptic––indeed, Stroud's major complaint against Moore seems to
be that Moore has declined to do any such thing; Moore has nothing more
to say than that skepticism is wrong because he, Moore, knows “this is
a pencil.” The very point I want to make here is that the Moorean
argument, or something very much like it, can supplement and strengthen
the presentation of an alternative, nonskeptical theory of
knowledge. Once we have two alternative, initially plausible
epistemological theories before us, if one of them is consistent with
our everyday, prephilosophical beliefs about what people know, while
the other is radically revisionary, this fact becomes a strong argument
in favor of the former. In the following chapters of this book, I
present precisely such a theory––a theory that maintains our common
sense beliefs about perception, knowledge, and justification to a
greater extent even than most nonskeptical philosophers would think
possible.”
(SVP, p. 44)
Comments
1. My view is that the fact that something is a pre-philosophical
belief does not ultimately have any epistemological weight. One
has to investigate whether the pre-philosophical belief is justified or
not.
2. The key to such an investigation, moreover, is bringing the concept
of logical probability to bear upon the question – unless the belief is
one that is justified via direct acquaintance with a state of affairs
that is a truthmaker for the proposition in question.