PHIL
1200 – Contemporary Social Problems (honors)
Spring 2020
Prof. Chris Heathwood
University of Colorado Boulder
What
We Did Each Day
(or plan/hope to do)
----- WEEK 1 -----
Tu 1/14:
First
day stuff: introduction, syllabus.
Th 1/16:
Went
through more of syllabus. Explained card system.
Under the
heading of "4. Reading" under "Requirements" portion of
syllabus, we discussed some of the key elements to look for in
reading philosophy. For example, questions
(such as "Is abortion morally permissible?" or, better
formulated, "Under what conditions, if any, is abortion
morally permissible").
Also theses or claims, such as
"Slavery is morally wrong," and whether these claims are moral
claims or non-moral claims.
Also moral principles, which we
defined as statements that say that a certain kind of act
always have a certain moral status.
Speaking of moral status, we discussed the
three main moral statuses that actions can have: permissible,
impermissible (or wrong), and obligatory.
We also noted that, in addition to evaluating actions, we
always evaluate people and states of affairs.
To arrive at an example of a moral principle, we began with
the particular moral judgment that cheating on your
partner is wrong, and then asked ourselves, "Why is this
wrong?" One answer was: because cheating on your
partner will hurt their feelings. And to
derive the conclusion that cheating on your partner is wrong
from the claim that cheating on your partner will hurt their
feelings, we need this moral principle: hurting someone's
feeling is always wrong.
Also arguments, which we defined as sequences
of statements, the last of which (the conclusion) is supposed
to follow from the others (the premises).
We stated the explanation of the wrongness of cheating on your
partner in the form of an argument.
We noted two ways in which to evaluate arguments: (i) in terms
of whether their premises, if true, really do guarantee that
the conclusion would also have to be true, and (ii) in terms
of whether their premises are in fact true.
Also, counterexamples: We noted that the
premises of of the cheating-on-your-partner argument were both
generalizations, and we discussed counterexamples to the
premise that cheating on your partner will hurt their
feelings.
To think about for next time: counterexamples to the premise
that hurting someone's feeling is always wrong
----- WEEK 2 -----
Tu 1/21:
- Discussed counterexamples to both
premises in this argument:
P1. Cheating on your partner hurts their feelings.
P2. Hurting people’s feelings is wrong.
C. It’s wrong to cheat on your partner.
- Defined 'validity' and 'soundness'
- To say that an argument is valid
is to say that if its premises are true, then
its conclusion must also be true.
- To say that an argument is sound
is to say (i) that it is valid and (ii) that its premises
are in fact true.
- Two examples of "Accounts or
Theories of Some Phenomenon" from ch. 3: Lauren's accounts of
being human and being alive:
- a being is human just in
case it has genetic material sufficient to make it a member
of Homo Sapiens
- a being is alive just in
case it has properties 2-7 on p. 14.
- Lauren’s First Anti-Abortion
Argument
P1. The embryos and fetuses that come into being when a woman
gets pregnant are both human and alive from the moment of
conception.
[from her accounts of being
human and being alive above]
P2. It’s wrong to kill a being that is both human and alive.
[as she puts it: “Taking human
life is wrong” (p. 16)]
C. Therefore, from the moment of conception it’s wrong to kill
the embryos and fetuses that come into being when a woman gets
pregnant.
[note: this is pretty much
equivalent to saying that abortion is wrong]
- Alex's Objection to Lauren’s First
Anti-Abortion Argument
- The (plausible) judgment that
Alex wants us to make: it's just as wrong to kill Frodo (or
Neytiri or Jar Jar Binks) as it is to kill us
- Alex seems to think this is
inconsistent with P2 of Lauren’s First Anti-Abortion
Argument
- But
it's not. He seems to be interpreting her P2 as
saying this: "the only thing it's wrong to kill is
something that is human and alive." But this is not
what P2 is saying. So this is a bad objection to Lauren’s First Anti-Abortion
Argument.
- Lauren's (better) objection to her
own argument:
- Cancer cells in human beings are
both human and alive, but it's not wrong to kill them (also
skin cells, blood cells, etc.)
- This shows that P2 of Lauren’s
First Anti-Abortion Argument is false.
- It does NOT show that the conclusion
of that argument is false, or that abortion is ok.
Th 1/23:
- Finished syllabus.
- Reviewed Lauren’s First
Anti-Abortion Argument, which we now formulated like this:
P1. Embryos are both human and alive
P2. It’s wrong to kill anything that is both human and alive
C. So, it’s wrong to kill embryos.
- Reviewed why Alex's counterexample
to P2 (involving characters like Frodo) is no good and why
Lauren's own counterexample to P2 (involving human cancer
cells) seems better.
- Discussed an objection to the idea
that the example of cancer cells is a good counterexample to
P2; this objection claimed that cancer cells are not human; so
this objection requires giving an alternative account (to
Lauren's) of what it is to be human
- Discussed this question: if a
person rejects P2 of Lauren’s First Anti-Abortion Argument,
and thus they think that it is an unsound argument, are they
thereby saying that the reject the conclusion of the
argument?
- Answer:
No. You can reject an argument as unsound even
though you think it's conclusion is true.
- This
is related to the fact that there are unsound
arguments for true conclusions.
- An
example of a valid but unsound argument for a true
conclusion:
P1. The earth has a circumference.
P2. Only spherical things have circumferences.
C. Thus, the earth is spherical.
(This argument is valid, and it has a true conclusion. But
it is unsound; that's because P2 is false [circles also
have circumferences].)
- A
lesson of C3PO, Neytiri, and Frodo is not that P2 of
Lauren’s First Anti-Abortion
Argument is false (though other examples do this),
but rather that they get us to see this fact: the reason it
is wrong to kill us is the same reason that it would be
wrong to kill C3PO, Neytiri, or Frodo.
- And
what you and I and C3PO, Neytiri, and Frodo all have in
common is nothing biological (like being human) but
something psychological (like being conscious, using
language, knowing and believing things, desiring things,
being self-conscious, having a will, using reasoning (p.
19)).
- Let's
preliminarily call beings that have these features
'persons'.
- Since
what makes killing you or I wrong and killing C3PO,
Neytiri, or Frodo wrong is the same thing, and what we
all have in common is that we are all persons, our
being persons must be a big part of the explanation of
why it's wrong to kill us.
- A moral
principle that embodies this idea will look something
like this:
(WKP) If x is an innocent person, then killing x is
morally wrong—unless such treatment prevents an
extraordinary catastrophe.
- What
is meant by "catastrophe"? See p. 8:
"suppose
some terrorists have set the countdown on an atomic
bomb somewhere underneath the streets of Manhattan.
The FBI locates the bomb with two minutes remaining,
only to discover that the terrorists have assembled
a human “shield” around the bomb, out of innocent
kidnapped people. Removing this shield without loss
of life would require hours of painstaking
lockpicking. Some will surely say that the FBI can
destroy the human shield in order to save millions
of people who would otherwise perish."
----- WEEK 3 -----
Tu 1/28:
Did Exam #1, then
onto Chapter 4:
- WKP: If x is
an innocent person, then killing x is morally wrong—unless
such treatment prevents an extraordinary catastrophe.
- First
Account of Personhood:
Persons are beings currently have or
exemplify all the features on list L (p. 21)
- Problem
for the combination of WKP and First Account of
Personhood: it cannot explain why it's wrong to kill
sleeping people
- The
Capacity-Oriented Account of Personhood:
persons are beings
with the capacity to have all the items on list L.
- Problem
for the combination of WKP and Capacity-Oriented
Account of Personhood (aka the Silver
Principle): it cannot explain why it's wrong to kill
people in temporary comas.
- The
Golden Principle (GP):
If x is innocent and x has or will
have — if not interfered with and allowed to develop — the
capacities listed in L,
then it is morally wrong to destroy x—unless doing so is
necessary to prevent a catastrophe.
- Reason to believe in GP: it can
explain why it's wrong
to kill people in temporary comas.
- Let a
‘normal fetus’ = a fetus (i) that has a reasonable shot at
reaching personhood (as opposed to, for example, a fetus
that has a very serious disease or disability or a fetus
whose mother/parents live in very extreme and unstable
social or environmental circumstances, such as war); and
(ii) whose birth would not lead to a horrible catastrophe.
“The Antiabortion Argument” (cf. pp. 29-30)
P1. GP
P2. Normal fetuses are innocent.
P3. Normal fetuses will have — if not interfered with and
allowed to develop — the capacities listed in L.
P4. Destroying normal fetuses won’t help prevent any
catastrophes.
C. Thus, it’s morally wrong to destroy normal fetuses.
Th 1/30:
Returned Exam #1
Extended discussion of “The
Antiabortion Argument” above:
- One possibly important difference
between temporary coma patients and fetuses: temporary coma
patients used to be persons, but fetuses have never been
persons.
- Why this might matter morally:
beings that were persons (such as the coma patient) had
hopes and dreams and plans about the future that will be
dashed if they are not allowed to become persons again, but
being that were never persons (such as fetuses) don't have
this
- How to revise GR so that it
reflects this idea: it needs to say, "If x is innocent and x
either has or both will have and had the capacities
listed in L . . . ."
- such a principle can get the
result we want in the coma case without implying that it's
wrong to kill fetuses.
- though note that this would
just be an alternative way to explain why it's wrong to
kill coma patients; it wouldn't show that the “The
Antiabortion Argument” is unsound
- A counter-thought in support of
the idea that it's worse to kill fetuses than it is to kill
adults who have been persons: fetuses lose more when they
die than do adults (and this is why we would give the last
remaining spot on a lifeboat to a 9-year-old over a 90-year
old.
- Just what is meant by "P2. Normal
fetuses are innocent," and why the argument does not seem
vulnerable with regard to this premise
- The Contraception Objection
- Q: Which premise is this
attacking?
A: It is attacking the Golden Principle (P1)
- It is saying that GP implies
that acting so as to destroy an ovum instead of helping it
develop into a person is morally wrong; thus contraception
and other ways to avoid conceiving a child each month are
wrong.
- But it's not clear that GP
implies this.
- GP implies this only if each
of us was once an ovum.
- But it doesn't seem very
plausible to think that each of us was once an ovum.
It seems very plausible that each of us was once a
newborn, and also that each of us was once a fetus, and
also that each of us was once an
embryo, and perhaps even that each of us was once
a zygote; but not that each of us was once an ovum.
- Thus, “The
Antiabortion Argument” seems to avoid the Contraception
Objection
----- WEEK 4 -----
Tu 2/4:
Questionnaire Results
- Class results for main question
- Gallup
poll
- Some of the reasons behind your
answers:
- “an embryo and fetus are alive
from the moment of conception, making an abortion an act of
murder
- But consider: weeds are alive,
but killing them is not murder
- Also: human cancer cells are
both human and alive, but killing them is not murder
- “I don't find the murder of a
living being that lacks a fair amount of perception or
ability to communicate to be comparable to the murder of a
being that does"
- But consider: people in
temporary comas lack a fair amount of perception or
ability to communicate, but murdering them is comparable
to the murder of a being that doesn't lack these abilities
- “In some cases the family may
not be able to raise a child due to many reasons, therefore
a typical abortion should be accepted under specific
circumstances”
“if a woman becomes pregnant and cannot raise the kid in a
safe, healthy environment because the woman is mentally ill,
financially unstable, or a substance abuser, it might be
even worse to bring a child into a world that is already so
disadvantaged”
- But consider: if an embryo is
the kind of thing that it is generally wrong to kill (like
a normal 10-year-old or a normal 30-year-old), then it
doesn't seem like these justifications would be sufficient
to have an abortion; they wouldn't be sufficient for
killing a 10-year-old
- “a woman’s body is her own and
should be regarded that way”
“I don’t think it should be anyone’s decision but the
woman’s as to what happens to their body”
- Even if an embryo is a being
with a full right to life? If an embryo has a right
to life, how can it be ok to kill it (other than if, say,
your own life is at stake?
- In Judith Thomson's famous
1971 paper, she tried to show, using the following
example, that having a right to life does not entail
having a right to the use of another person's body, even
if that is required to go on living:
“let
me ask you to imagine this. You wake up in the
morning and find yourself back
to back in bed with an
unconscious violinist. A famous unconscious violinist. He has been found to have a fatal
kidney ailment, and the Society of Music Lovers has
canvassed all the available medical records and found
that you alone have the right blood type to help. They
have therefore kidnapped you, and last night the
violinist’s circulatory system was plugged into yours,
so that your kidneys can be used to extract poisons from
his blood as well as your own. The director of the
hospital now tells you, ‘Look, we’re sorry the Society
of Music Lovers did this to you – we would never have
permitted it if we had known. But still, they did it,
and the violinist now is plugged into you. To unplug you
would be to kill him. But never mind, it’s only for nine
months. By then he will have recovered from his ailment,
and can safely be unplugged from you” (Judith
Thomson, "A
Defense of Abortion" (1971)).
Introduction to Boonin book:
- Case of McFall vs. Shimp
- Poll on whether Shimp has a moral
obligation to save McFall's life by giving him some of his
bone marrow
- Poll on whether it is ok for the
state to force Shimp to donate his bone marrow in order to
save McFall's life
- no one in the class thought that
it is ok for the state to do this
- Boonin aims to show that, just as
it is not ok for the state to force Shimp to donate his bone
marrow in order to save McFall's life, it is not ok for the
state to force a pregnant woman to let the fetus inside her
use her body in order to keep the fetus alive -- and that this
is true even if abortion is in fact morally wrong.
Th 2/6
Remarks on Ch. 6 from Abortion: A
Dialogue:
- What are people (and the Supreme
Court) wrangling over when they wrangle over whether the fetus
is a person?
- Answer: they must be using a
new, third sense of the term, a moral sense
- Three senses of the word 'person':
- 'Person' in the biological sense
It means: member of Homo Sapiens
(this is what I think the word means in most or all ordinary
(non-philosophical) contexts)
- 'Person' in the psychological
sense
It means (at least roughly): has the features in L (or at least
the capacity to have them)
(we need this sense of the term to be able to group you and
me and Frodo and Neytiri and C3PO together with respect to
something very important that we share)
- 'Person'
in the moral sense
It means: has a full right to life or full
moral status (the same right to life or moral status as is
had by a normal human adult)
- Four account of what it takes to
be a person in the moral sense
- Basing moral status in
biology:
x is a person in the moral sense just in case x is a
person in the biological sense (cf. Lauren’s first
anti-abortion argument)
- Frodo: ⨉
- Coma Patient: ✓
- Infants: ✓
- Abortion: suggests it's wrong
- Basing
moral status in fancy psychology:
x is a person in the moral sense just in case x is a
person in the psychological
sense
- Frodo: ✓
- Coma Patient: ⨉
- Infants: ⨉
- Abortion: suggests it's ok
- Basing moral
status in present or future fancy psychology:
- Frodo: ✓
- Coma Patient: ✓
- Infants: ✓
- Abortion: suggests it's wrong
- Basing moral
status in present fancy psychology or future and
past fancy psychology:
- Frodo: ✓
- Coma Patient: ✓
- Infants: ⨉
- Abortion: suggests it's ok
- A natural and common thought about
the abortion debate:
abortion is morally permissible iff the fetus is not a person
in the moral sense (i.e., does not have a right to life)
- But Thomson's case Famous
Violinist casts doubt on this: it purports to show
that even if a being is a person in the moral sense (and so
has a right to life), that does not itself mean that it has
the right to whatever it needs to go on living
Boonin:
- “the fact that someone is a person with a right
to life doesn’t mean they have the right to use another’s
person body, even if they need to use that person’s body in
order to go on living” (Boonin, p. 9).
- Is Boonin here saying that
people with a right to life never have the right to
use another person’s body?
No.
- Let's try to think of cases
(having nothing to do with pregnancy or abortion) in which
(i) someone has a right to life, (ii) the only way they can
stay alive is by using another person’s body, and (iii) in
this case they do have the right to use that
person’s body:
- No take-backs on kidney
donation
- Someone, x, is responsible for
the fact that another person, y, is in need of the use of
another person's body, and x is the only suitable match
for this
- conjoined twins case
- Posthumous organ donation
----- WEEK 5 -----
Tu 2/11:
Exam #2
Review from last week:
- The natural and common thought
about the abortion debate: the idea that abortion is morally
permissible iff the fetus is not a person in the moral sense
(i.e., does not have a right to life).
- How Thomson’s thought experiment,
Famous Violinist, should at least give us pause when it
comes to this natural thought.
- How the case of McFall v.
Shimp also does this, and, in addition, seems to show
something about what the law should be.
- But: this does not show that
abortion is ok, nor that it should be legal; just that even if
the fetus has a full right to life, that is not sufficient
show that the fetus has the right to use the mother’s body. So
the pro-lifer will have to show that the fetus has more than
the mere right to life; she will have to show that the fetus
has the right to use its mother’s body to be kept alive.
Boonin ch. 3:
- Assumption for remainder of
abortion topic: fetuses are persons in the moral sense (i.e.,
they have a right to life) from the moment of conception.
- Ways in which case of Shimp and
case of Alice are analogous:
- McFall and Al:
- both are innocent
- both are persons with a full
right to life
- both will die unless they make
use of a certain other person’s body in a pretty invasive
way
- Shimp
and Alice:
- Each
is in a situation in which, through no fault of their
own, there is a person who needs to use their body in
order to stay alive, and only their body will work (no
one else can keep the person alive)
- An Argument by Analogy from the
Case of Shimp to the Case of Alice
P1. It would be wrong for the state to force Shimp to let
McFall use Shimp’s body.
P2. The state’s forcing Shimp to let McFall use Shimp’s body
is morally analogous to (or “morally on a par” with) the
state’s forcing Alice to let Al use Alice’s body.
C. Thus, it would be wrong for the state to force Alice to let
Al use Alice’s body.
- The significance of this
conclusion
Th 2/13:
Argument by Analogy for the View that Abortion Should be Legal
in Cases of Rape (Alice)
- Does this argument commit Boonin
to saying that Alice’s decision isn’t a big deal, that it is a
trivial decision?
- Or that it wouldn’t a selfless and
kind and praiseworthy for her to choose not to have an
abortion?
The Technique of Variant Cases
- To object to P2,
what need to identify a difference between the two cases that
would show that the cases are morally different (and so what
is right or wrong in one case is not right or wrong in the
other case)
- as we often put
it, your job is to come up with a morally relevant
difference between the two cases.
----- WEEK 6 -----
TUE FEB 18:
Guest lecture on Hedonism:
The Concept of Well-Being:
- Feldman's crib test
- Fletcher's kidney or blood
- Intrinsic vs. instrumental value
- An initial list of possible
intrinsic well-being goods
Hedonism
- the theory stated
- the concept of a person's hedonic
level
- an argument for hedonism: Raj on
the rollercoaster
The Experience Machine Objection to
Hedonism
THU FEB 20:
Reminder of where we’re at and
conclusion of discussion of abortion for the purposes of sex
selection and in cases of fetal abnormality:
- Reminder: Boonin's overarching
goal: to defend the idea that, even if we assume that a fetus
is a person with a full right to life — and even if we think
that abortion might very well be morally wrong — abortion
should nevertheless be legal; and it should be legal (a)
regardless of how the woman got pregnant (so
even if neither she nor her partner used birth control and
they are in effect using abortion itself as birth control),
and (b) regardless of the reason she wants to get an
abortion.
- Argument based on cases of
Dorothy and Thought It Was Roberta
- Argument
based on cases of Elaine and McFall Has Down Syndrome
- Other kinds of argument for the
view that abortion should be legal regardless of
the reason the woman wants to get an abortion:
- if
the state allowed abortions only for certain reasons, then
the state would have to ask all women their
reasons, and this would be very invasive and would violate
their privacy;
- it
would be too hard to enforce a law that forbade abortion
depending on the woman's reason for wanting one; it is too
hard to know this.
Late-term abortion / abortion after
viability:
- Argument by Analogy for the
View that Elective Abortion Should Not be Legal after
Viability (Francine and McFall Cured)
:
P1. The state should not let Shimp kill McFall in McFall
Cured.
P2. The state’s letting Shimp kill McFall in McFall Cured
would be morally analogous to the state’s letting Francine
kill Frank.
C. Thus, the state should not let Francine kill Frank.
- SUPPOSED TO SHOW: elective
abortion should not be legal after viability.
- NOTE: this argument cannot be
found explicitly in the Boonin, but the materials for it
are there
- Attempt to find morally relevant
differences between Francine
and McFall Cured:
- One potentially morally relevant
difference: If Francine does not have an abortion, that it
will be a serious issue and burden for her, but if Shimp
does not kill McFall in McFall Cured, it will not be
a
serious issue and burden for for him.
- Problem for this: consider
this case: Fiona has a two-year-old son, Finn. Fiona no
longer wants to be a mother. Furthermore, if Finn were to
continue to exist at all (even in someone else's care),
this would a serious issue and burden for Fiona.
So Fiona wants to kill Finn.
- It seems rather obvious that
the state should not allow Fiona to do this to Finn. But
if the continued existence of Frank being a serious
issue and burden for Francine would make it the case
that the state should allow Francine to have an
abortion, then it should do the same for Fiona. But
because it should obviously not do this for Fiona, this
shows that it should not do it for Francine.
- (Another possible problem for
this, possibly to discuss next time: variant on Shimp
case in which McFall is in Shimp's care)
- Another
potentially morally relevant difference: Disconnecting
from McFall in a way that doesn’t harm McFall is no more
of a burden on Shimp than disconnecting from McFall in a
way that would kill McFall;
but disconnecting from Frank in a way that doesn’t harm
Frank (this would be via a C-section) may be much more of
a burden on Francine than would disconnecting from Frank
in a way that kills Frank (e.g., via the late-term
abortion procedure (“dilation and extraction”) described
in the Economist article).
- (we'll
discuss this more on Monday)
----- WEEK 7 -----
TUE FEB 25:
Had Exam #3
Feticide:
- The grisly
Longmont case, and how Boonin's view can simultaneously
allow the attacker in this case to be charged with murder (for
killing the fetus) even while the mother in this case retained
the right to have an abortion (at least before viability).
Viability: finish up discussion of
Argument by Analogy for the View that Elective Abortion Should
Not be Legal after Viability (Francine and McFall Cured)
:
- Possibly morally relevant
difference between Francine and McFall
Cured: Disconnecting from McFall in a way that doesn’t
harm McFall is no more of a burden on Shimp than disconnecting
from McFall in a way that would kill him (if there even is
such a way), but disconnecting from Frank in a way that
doesn’t harm Frank (that would be via a C-section)
may be much more of a burden on Francine than would
disconnecting from Frank in a way that kills Frank (e.g., via
the late-term abortion procedure described in the Economist
article).
- Is this less burdensome than
a C-section? Well, a C-section is an invasive
surgical procedure that carries the usual risks of invasive
surgery and that requires the usual sort of recovery.
Maybe some women would not find this any more burdensome
than the “dilation and extraction” procedure above. If
so, then for them, the diff above would not actually be a
real diff (let alone a morally relevant one). But
let’s imagine that Francine hates surgery, hates having
incisions in her, hates any kind of anesthesia, and really
really doesn’t want surgery. She’d much much rather
have the other method of getting Frank out of her, a method
that is more like regular, vaginal birth and unlike the
C-section. Of course, doing it that way will kill
Frank.
- Variant case to test this:Suppose
Shimp agrees to hook up to McFall. The full procedure,
the one to leave McFall in the best shape, lasts 9
hours. After 7 hours, Shimp changes his mind. He no
longer wants to be attached to McFall. So far, this is just
the case McFall Cured. But now suppose that the way
the machine works, it is kind of an ordeal to detach. If
McFall detaches now, there are two options: (i) in order to
detach in a way that won’t harm McFall, Shimp has to detach
from the machine in a way that will mutilate his own body and
risks an infection (this way of detaching is harmless to
McFall); (ii) or there is
a way to detach from the machine that, while still an ordeal
for Shimp, requires no mutilation of his body and no risk of
infection (this way of detaching would kill McFall).
- If Shimp wants the second
option, should the state allow it?
THU FEB 27:
See Handout
on the Responsibility Objection.
----- WEEK 8 -----
TUE MAR 3:
Finish
discussion of Responsibility Objection:
RP1 and RP2 applied to two cases:
Fireworks:
- what our
intuitions are about it (McFall has
a right to use Shimp's body);
- what RP1
implies about it (nothing);
- what RP2
implies about it (McFall has a right to use Shimp's body).
Barbara:
- what RP1
implies about it (Bob has a right to use Shimp's body);
- what RP2
implies about it (nothing).
Everyone can perhaps agree that RP2
is true. But Boonin's position will stand or fall on
whether RP1 is true.
Boonin's counterexample to RP1:
Toxic Heimlich:
- what our
intuitions are about it (McFall does
not have a right to use Shimp's body);
- what RP1
implies about it (McFall does not have a
right to use Shimp's body).
Two Arguments representing Boonin's
position:
Boonin’s Counterexample to RP1 in
Argument Form:
P1. If RP1 is true, then, in Toxic Heimlich, McFall has
the right to use Shimp’s body.
P2. But in Toxic Heimlich McFall does not have the right to use
Shimp’s body
C. So, RP1 is not true.
An Argument by Analogy Based on
the Case of Toxic Heimlich:
P1. It would be wrong for the
state to force Shimp to let McFall use Shimp’s body in Toxic
Heimlich.
P2. The state’s forcing Shimp to let McFall use Shimp’s body in Toxic
Heimlich is morally analogous to the state’s
forcing Barbara to let Bob use Barbara’s body.
C. Thus, it would be wrong for the state to force Barbara to let
Bob use Barbara’s body.
Objections?:
- Andi's objection:
- Possibly morally relevant
difference between Toxic Heimlich and Barbara:
Shimp had a moral obligation to do the act that led to
McFall's being in need, but Barbara did not have a moral
obligation to do the act that led to Bob's being in
need. (Maybe this excuses Shimp and gets him off the
hook in a way that is not true of Barbara.)
- Maren's proposal for testing
it. Variant case:
Unwanted Heimlich: suppose McFall told Shimp not to
give him the Heimlich, because McFall didn't want to catch
aplastic anemia, but suppose Shimp ignores that and saves
McFall anyway. McFall later gets aplastic
anemia.
Now our question about this: Does McFall have a right
to use Shimp's body in Unwanted Heimlich?
Answer: maybe so. And if so, this suggests that
Andi's objection may be a good one.
- Aniela's objection
- Possibly morally relevant
difference between Toxic Heimlich and Barbara:
McFall existed before any of this but Bob did not.
- (We ran out of time / weren't
sure how to test this)
THU MAR
5:
- Recall
The Alice Argument
P1. It would be wrong for the state to force Shimp to let
McFall use Shimp’s body.
P2. The state’s forcing Shimp to let McFall use Shimp’s body
is morally analogous to the state’s forcing Alice to let Al
use Alice’s body.
C. Thus, it would be wrong for the state to force Alice to
let Al use Alice’s body.
- Here is a
possibly morally relevant difference b/w McFall/Shimp
and Alice:
it would be unnatural for Shimp
to use his bone marrow to keep McFall alive, but it would be
natural for Alice to use her uterus to keep Al alive.
- Why it is
hard to test this difference is morally relevant using the
technique of variant cases
- But one
way to try to do so is to vary the controversial case,
the Alice case
- A different
way to assess the objection: formulate it as an argument,
and evaluate that argument:
The Natural Right Argument:
P1. The purpose of a woman’s uterus is to gestate babies.
P2. If the purpose of a woman’s uterus is to gestate babies,
then a fetus has the right to use its mother’s uterus.
P3. If a fetus has the right to use its mother’s uterus,
then it would be wrong for Alice not to let Al use her
uterus.
P4. If it would be wrong for Alice not to let Al use her
uterus, then it would be ok for the state to force Alice to
let Al use her uterus.
C. Therefore, it would be ok for the state to force Alice to
let Al use her uterus.
- If this
argument is sound, then the Alice Argument is unsound (for
their conclusions conflict)
- Clearly no analogous argument
for the conclusion that it would be ok for the state to
force Shimp to let McFall use Shimp’s body would be sound,
because the analog of P2 of such an argument -- namely, that
if the purpose of a bone marrow is to produce blood cells,
then anyone has the right to use another person's bone
marrow -- is a non-starter.
- So this would suggest that the
difference identified above is indeed morally relevant
- Responses to the Natural Right
Argument:
- Maren's my-sister's keeper
parody argument:
P1. Anna's purpose is to provide bone marrow and eventually
a kidney to Kate (after all, Anna was conceived by her
parents for this purpose).
P2: If Anna's purpose is to provide bone marrow and
eventually a kidney to Kate, then Kate has a right to Anna's
bone marrow and kidney.
C. Therefore, Kate has a right to Anna's bone marrow and
kidney.
Maren's point is that this conclusion about Anna is absurd,
and thus P2 must be false. And thus P2 of the Natural
Right argument must be false.
- Andi's reply to Maren: But
your parody argument involves a different kind of purpose,
and so we can't draw any conclusions about the Natural
Right Argument from your parody argument; in your
argument, the purpose is based simply in the parents'
intentions in conceiving Anna; but in the Natural Right
Argument, the purpose is based something different (either
God or evolution).
- Boonin's response to the Natural
Right Argument with P1 has a theistic basis:
Advocates of the Natural Right Argument when P1 has a
theistic basis will think that it is wrong to go against a
thing's purpose, and this is because doing so violates God's
will. So, depending on their religious tradition, they
will think that acts like contraception, masturbation, and
oral sex are wrong. Fine. But now ask: what is
the rationale for P4? It is presumably this: if
some act is wrong due to its violating God's will, then it
is ok for the state to outlaw that act.
But then advocates of the theistically-based Natural
Right Argument will have to say that it is ok for the
state to outlaw contraception,
masturbation, and oral sex. But presumably they
don't want to say that.
- Heathwood's reply to this: Maybe
Boonin's opponent can appeal to the idea that if the
act goes against natural purposes and is very
seriously wrong (say, because it’s a matter of
life and death), then it’s ok for the state to outlaw
it. So we'd change P3 and P4 to this:
P3′. If a fetus has the right to use its mother’s
uterus, then it would be very seriously wrong
for Alice not to let Al use her uterus. [very
seriously wrong because it would be a matter of life
and death]
P4′. If it would be very seriously wrong for Alice
not to let Al use her uterus, then it would be ok for
the state to force Alice to let Al use her uterus.
The latter premise is based on the principle that if
some act is very seriously wrong due to its
violating God's will and being a matter of life
and death, then it is ok for the state to
outlaw that act. This principle will not
imply that would be ok for the state to
outlaw contraception,
masturbation, and oral sex.
- Maren's
rejoinder to Heathwood's reply: But this
rationale for P4′ would still
involve an objectionable influence of
religion into the law; because there
is so much disagreement about religion
and about what God wants (if God
exists at all), we should not let this
determine the law.
----- WEEK 9 -----
TUE MAR 10:
Exam #4
THU MAR 12:
Abortion Restrictions
Handout on Boonin Part III: Why Abortion Should Be Less
Restricted
Discussion of Parental Consent and Notification
----- WEEK 10 -----
TUE MAR 17:
Author Q&A with David Boonin
THU MAR 19:
Intro remarks:
- new topic, but structural similiarity to
abortion:
- dissimiliarity: the impermissive
view on abortion is a view categorized as part of the right,
but for animals the left
- another dissimilarity: but the
book we read for the abortion topic (at least the second book)
supported the view that most or all of us already held, but
the book we are reading for this topic argues against the view
most or all of us already held.
Examination of survey results:
"Chalkboard"
from class this day
[[[[[[[[[[ SPRING BREAK
]]]]]]]]]]]
----- WEEK 11 -----
TUE MAR 31:
Ethical Vegetarianism: It
is wrong to eat meat in circumstances we normally actually face.
The Argument from Pain and Suffering
P1. It is wrong to knowingly inflict a great deal of pain and
suffering on others, just for the sake of getting relatively minor
benefits for yourself.
P2. The meat industry inflicts a great deal of pain and suffering
on animals, for the sake of comparatively minor benefits.
C. Therefore, the meat industry is doing something wrong.
Examination of P2:
- What sorts of pain and suffering
is P2 talking about?
- What sorts of benefits is P2
talking about?
- gustatory pleasure
- are there also health benefits?
Evidently not:
(I didn't post today's "Chalkboard"
because it consisted solely of the statements of Ethical
Vegetarianism and The Argument from Pain and Suffering, which I
already stated above.)
THU APR 2:
"Chalkboard"
----- WEEK 12 -----
TUE APR 7:
Working out M’s meat-industry-friendly position: M1, M2, M3,
M4, and M5.
Chalkboard
THU APR 9:
Discussed Philosophy
Paper FAQ in preparation for our paper.
The Paying-Other-People Argument
Chalkboard
----- WEEK 13 -----
TUE APR 14:
Announcement: deadline for having paper topic approved: TUE
APR 21
Chalkboard
THU APR 16:
Chalkboard
----- WEEK 14 -----
TUE APR 21:
Student-led, free-form discussion of random issues from book. Some topics
discussed:
- the moral status of insects / whether insects feel pain
- objections to factory farming not having to do with the animal
welfare (e.g., climate change, risks of pandemics, overuse of
antibiotics)
- ostroveganism and the way in which it seems especially
principled
- the mismatch between how strong the reasons to be against the
practice appear to be together with the popularity of the
practice
- the morality of hunting, especially as compared with the
morality of buying meat from stores
THU APR 23
Chalkboard