SOCIAL CONTRACT IS BENEFICIAL
CONTRACT JUSTIFIES LIBERAL DEMOCRATIC
INSTITUTIONS
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.156.
But, by hypothesis (the hypothesis
of modest contractarianism), we assume that our contractors value security
(otherwise they wouldn't want government at all). Hence we have a contractarian
argument for the usual liberal-democratic safeguards against abuse of power,
and for a share in its exercise by ordinary citizens, for example, through
representative institutions.
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT WAS A HUGE ADVANCE
IN HUMAN EQUALITY
MURRAY FORSYTH, PROFESSOR OF INTERNATIONAL
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF LEICESTER, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS,
DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.37.
But such criticism should not be
allowed to obscure the main point, which is that the notion of a social
contract implied and embodied a huge advance in the idea of human equality,
and that the very ambiguity in the words 'men' and 'man', their simultaneous
connotation of males and humanity, made it possible for the theory to be
expanded beyond the limited assumptions of its founders. The emergence
of the notion of the social contract is hence linked intimately with the
emergence of the idea of the equality of human beings. It is the political
expression of this idea, developing alongside, and interweaving with, the
religious and economic expressions of it.
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FOLLOWS FROM
THE CONCEPT OF HUMAN RIGHTS
JOHN CHARVET, READER IN POLITICS,
LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS, DAVID
BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.178.
Let us suppose, then, that after
entering upon the process of abstraction through which we arrive at the
idea of our general human interests we also come to hold that we possess
natural or human rights in respect of them; in other words, that persons
as such, in virtue of being ends in themselves independently of their membership
of particular communities, can claim rights to life and liberty and rights
of access to resources. In that case we must believe ourselves to be immediately
part of a universal ethical order the basic units of which are individual
human beings with rights. The idea of such a universal order is given an
initial elaboration in classic contractarian theory in the form of the
notion of a state of nature. This notion has subsequently been much ridiculed,
not least by those writers in the communitarian tradition. But it has been
given powerful contemporary reformulations by Nozick and Gauthier, and
can, I think, be shown to be a necessary implication of the idea of a world
of natural or human rights.
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT EXISTS TO PROMOTE
INDIVIDUAL RIGHTS
GEORGE KATEB, AMHERST POLITICAL
SCIENTIST, DISSENT, SPRING 1986, P.169.
The agreement, the social contract,
is made and sustained for the sake of individual rights. We do not exist
for each other, that truly means that we do not exist for the sake of a
mystique. we owe each other respect for rights, with all the duties attaching
to such respect. If one gives up everything, it is not for the people,
but for the rights of other individuals, including the unborn.
CONTRACTARIANISM IS WORKABLE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.155.
Thus, a modest contractarianism
incorporating a modified veil of ignorance seems workable. It can, perhaps,
be taken further. It might be used, for example, to ground the Rawlsian
basic liberties (though not necessarily their priority); that is, a hypothetical
contract can be used to ground protection of these liberties, for societies
which value them. This may sound like arguing in a circle - basic liberties
should be safeguarded for those who value them, because they value them;
but it is not. The argument escapes circularity through the distinction
between values and the distribution of what is valued. Where members of
a society, by and large, value liberty, the device of hypothetical contract
plus (or including) a veil of ignorance yields the conclusion that (other
things equal) what is valued should be distributed in a particular way.
Whoever wants liberty is forced by the veil of ignorance to agree that
everyone ought to have it.
CONTRACTARIANISM IS USEFUL &
JUSTIFIES BASIC INSTITUTIONS
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.157.
If the foregoing argument has any
merit, it suggests that a modest hypothetical contractualism is not useless.
We may use it to think about our own society, at least if our society exhibits
a significant degree of consensus on values. I suggest that it does. Our
attitudes to security, both physical and economic, to liberty and to the
exercise of power are sufficiently similar to ground certain, rather general
conclusions about their distribution. If it is permissible, as suggested
by Mueller et al., to base a contractualist argument on the average attitude
of our society in these matters, more specific conclusions can be derived.
Broadly speaking, these conclusions constitute a justification of the political
institutions of liberal democracy, the free market, and the welfare state.
CONTRACT THEORY SUPPORTS RULE OF
LAW
ALLAN BLOOM, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO, THE CLOSING OF THE AMERICAN MIND, 1987, P.319.
The contract theorists (from whose
teachings the American form of government was derived) all taught that
the law must never be broken, that the strength of the law is the only
thing that keeps us away from the state of nature, therefore that risks
and dangers must be accepted for the sake of the law. Once the law is broken
with impunity, each man regains the right to any means he deems proper
or necessary in order to defend himself against the new tyrant, the one
who can break the law.
CONTRACTUALISM AIDS IN UNDERSTANDING
OPPRESSION
JEREMY WALDRON, PROFESSOR OF LAW,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO
RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.70.
Contractarianism has critical as
well as legitimizing resources. The strength of the theory is that it provides
a set of categories by which events like oppression and subjugation can
be evaluated negatively, and with which attempts to draw doctrines of obligation,
allegiance and legitimacy out of such a history can be resisted. It is
explicit in the moral categories of contractarianism that, as Locke puts
it, 'no-one can be . . . subjected to the Political Power of another, without
his own Consent'. The setting up of political institutions by force, or
the setting up or altering of institutions in a way that everyone could
not possibly agree to, has no effect whatever so far as the establishment
of obligation or political legitimacy are concerned.
GRADUAL DEVELOPMENT OF GOVT. STILL
SUBJECT TO CONTRACT STANDARDS
JEREMY WALDRON, PROFESSOR OF LAW,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO
RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.69.
A set of institutional arrangements
may evolve by gradual steps over a period of time; but if each step involves
elements of choice, deliberation and purpose, then the whole process takes
on an intentional flavor, becomes susceptible to intentionalist categories,
and may be evaluated in terms of human purposes in the way that contract
theory requires. This remains the case even if it is true - which it usually
is - that the whole process was not the subject of anyone's intentions
and that the overall direction of the development was unforeseen. That
is not a reason to withhold intentional evaluation from each - and therefore
all - of the steps in the process, since each step can at least be seen
as the upshot of intentional human action, and all subsequent steps remain
an open subject for our choice.
THE CONTRACT IS AN IDEAL, NOT A
HISTORICAL REALITY
JEREMY WALDRON, PROFESSOR OF LAW,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO
RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.51.
Modern contractarians accept without
question that most of the social and political institutions which interest
them are not in fact the upshot of any contract or agreement among those
whose lives they affect. They are happy to repudiate ideas like the state
of nature and the original contract as historical hypotheses, to regard
them, in Robert Nozick's phrase, as 'fact-defective' characterizations,
and to accept that the actual evolution of political society probably took
an entirely different course from the one the contract image suggests.
Many accept also that the legitimacy of the modern state and our obligations
to it do not depend on the reality of our consent or voluntary submission.
For example, John Rawls concedes, 'No society can . . . be a scheme of
cooperation which men enter voluntarily in a literal sense; each finds
himself placed at birth in some particular position in some particular
society'. To the extent that it is used at all, the social contract is
understood as a purely hypothetical construction: not an assumption of
fact but, as Kant described it, 'merely an idea of reason' that generates
the basis of a normative standard for testing laws and social arrangements.
We do not ask whether the arrangements were in fact agreed to; we ask instead
whether they could have been agreed to by people working out the basis
of a life together under conditions of initial freedom and equality. If
the answer is 'No', then we have a basis for condemning the institutions
in question as incompatible with the very ideas of freedom and equality,
quite apart from their actual origin or purpose.
CONTRACT IS FOR MORAL EVALUATION,
NOT HISTORICAL DESCRIPTION
JEREMY WALDRON, PROFESSOR OF LAW,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO
RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.63.
The contract story is not intended
as a historical description; it is intended rather as a moral tool for
historical understanding. It is the function of the political anthropology
to offer us an account of what actually happened; while the contract story
offers us the moral categories in terms of which what actually happened
is to be understood.
STATE OF NATURE NEED NEVER HAVE
EXISTED TO BE USEFUL
JOHN CHARVET, READER IN POLITICS,
LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS, DAVID
BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.179.
Nevertheless, given the cosmopolitan's
adherence to a system of universal individual rights the idea of the state
of nature without political divisions must have logical priority over the
reconstitution of the state within cosmopolitan theory. This does not involve
the belief that the state of nature ever existed, or even could exist without
complete disaster for the human race. Yet it is necessary to entertain
this idea in its social form as described above in order to see whether
the system of universal rights is compatible with the existence of a world
divided into formal complete associations. We may immediately conclude
from the contemplation of the idea that such associations are justified.
CONTRACT IS A METAPHOR, NOT A LITERAL
DESCRIPTION
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.2.
Before that, however, we need some
sharper analysis of the concept of contract. Contract is a legal term,
and the notion of the social or political contract postulates that political
obligation is analogous to the legal obligation of a party to a contract.
It must be stressed that this is an analogy, not an identity - it is not
postulated by contract theorists that political obligation is a legal obligation.
Indeed, since the function of social contract theory is to give an account
of politically organized society ('civil society', as many theorists have
called it), and civil law is itself one aspect of the latter, it would
be manifestly absurd to base political obligation on law in this sense.
Clearly it must rest on something prior to civil law; and the typical understanding
of contract theorists has been that the contractual obligation they postulate
is founded on natural law.
CONTRACTUALISM CALLS FOR MUTUAL
TOLERANCE AND LIMITS COERCION
DAVID WONG, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BRANDEIS, DEFENDING DIVERSITY, LAWRENCE FOSTER AND PATRICIA HERZOG, EDS.,
1994, P.13.
Thomas Nagel has argued for restraint
in the coercive exercise of political power when one is engaged in a particular
kind of intractable moral conflict. This liberal principle of tolerance
gains support from the contractualist idea that one should not impose arrangements,
institutions, and requirements on grounds that people could reasonably
reject, that is, when the disagreement comes down to a "bare confrontation
between personal points of view."
ALL CONTRACT THEORIES ASSUME NATURAL
FREEDOM
MURRAY FORSYTH, PROFESSOR OF INTERNATIONAL
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF LEICESTER, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS,
DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.38.
The core of the idea of equality
which is embodied in the contract theory is not, however, man's power to
kill, but rather the principle that all men are equally free. While - as
we shall see - not all the classical writers agreed exactly on the meaning
of this principle, they did agree on this: that each man, by right of nature,
that is, by right of his human character, rather than through the mediation
of other men, possessed the quality of freedom. Even Hobbes, who spoke
of equality in the grimly physical terms alluded to, also spoke of man's
inherent right to 'use his own power, as he will himself, for the preservation
of his own nature'. More concisely and trenchantly, he wrote that 'all
men equally, are by nature free'.
THE CONTRACTUAL STATE ISN'T TOTALITARIAN
OR MILITARISTIC
DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, PROFESSORS
OF POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS,
1994, P.16.
It would be anachronistic to attribute
to the contractarians who personified the state the totalitarian and militaristic
implications that have become associated with the German realists Trietscke
and Bernhardt. The person of the state for Pufendorf, to take just one
instance, had the modest objective of ensuring the security of its citizens,
and could have no justifiable expansionist ambitions. It was purportedly
subject to natural law and should always be motivated by the general rule:
'Let the safety of the people be the supreme law".
GOVERNMENTS ESTABLISHED BY FORCE
CAN BE UNDERSTOOD IN THE CONTRACT
JEREMY WALDRON, PROFESSOR OF LAW,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO
RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.70.
Thus, viewing events through the
template of the social contract story does not mean that we must view every
stage in the history of our political development as a legitimate contractual
step. It means simply that we should view it using contractarian categories,
and that means treating each step either as though it involved elements
of choice, consent and obligation, or as though it were an incident of
force, oppression and the persistence of a right to resist) and drawing
the appropriate conclusions. That is the choice that the contract approach
gives us for each stage in the process of our political development. We
make judgments, and the upshot of those judgments will contribute towards
an estimation of our moral position in relation to the political system
which is currently claiming our allegiance. No doubt this estimation will
be very complicated, but of course it is no part of the contractarian philosophy
to commit us to the view that political obligation and political legitimacy
are simple and straightforward issues.
CONSENSUAL STATES ARE CLEARLY MORE
LEGITIMATE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.88-9.
Hume is clearly right that no existing
state is directly founded on an original contract; nevertheless, one should
consider separately the problems arising from 'usurpation and conquest'
on the one hand, and from the peaceful continuation of states through successive
generations on the other. It is, after all, open to the contract theorist
to deny the legitimacy of states founded immediately or ultimately on violence,
precisely on the ground that such states are not based on consent (Locke
did just this)and while to Hume this leads to absurd (indeed dangerous)
results, everyone is not compelled to agree with him. This remains an open
question. It would be more difficult to deny the legitimacy of states which,
at first founded on an original contract, continue peacefully through successive
generations.
CONTRACTUALISM JUSTIFIES A STATE
GUARANTEED MINIMUM
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.152-3.
Is it then simply rational for
everyone to agree to a state-guaranteed social minimum? Not exactly-this
still depends on attitudes to risk, as does the level of the minimum (and
concomitant redistribution) that it would be rational to choose. These
attitudes vary from person to person, and from society to society. Nevertheless,
we can still defend a modest hypothetical contractualism; a contractualism
much more modest than traditional contract theory in the following ways.
Firstly, in so far as it derives specific conclusions, it must be admitted
that these will be applicable only to particular societies, not universally.
For example, only for societies where economic security is relatively highly
valued will the contractarian argument yield support for a social minimum.
Secondly, the conclusions cannot be too specific - thus, even in a society
in which people value economic security, not everyone puts the same value
on it, and so there is no single level of social minimum that can reflect
everyone's attitude. And thirdly, there are likely to be some people, even
in such a security-minded society, whose attitudes to risk are so positive
that, for them, acceptance of a social minimum is not rational at all.
In sum, this modest contractualism can hope to be persuasive only to the
great bulk of members of particular societies (not to all members of all
societies), and can only lay down rather general prescriptions. Thus, a
social contract argument applied to the countries of Western Europe in
the late twentieth century - societies where economic security is highly
valued - can be used to justify a relatively generous social minimum, but
not at any specific level, and certainly not the 'maximum minimum' prescribed
by Rawls. In the USA, perhaps, attitudes to risk are more positive, the
desire for security less strong and widespread, and for that country 'modest'
contractarianism prescribes a less generous minimum, or even conceivably
none at all.
CONTRACTARIANISM NEED NOT BE LIMITED
TO WESTERN SOCIETIES
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.160.
Yet, in principle, the application
of even modest contractarianism need not be confined to modern western
society; it should be applicable to any society that recognises the need
for a just resolution of conflicting individual interests. And if this
is not quite a universal applicability, perhaps it ought to be.
SOCIAL CONTRACT SEEKS WELFARE OF
ALL, NOT JUST SELF-INTERESTED
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.121-2.
In summary, so far as the issue
of self-interest is concerned, social contract theory occupies what might
be called a middle-of-the-road position. Up to a point, it appeals to the
self-interest of the individual (and certainly does not call fat self-abnegation),
in so far as self-interest is assumed to be the motive for contracting.
But the standard of legitimacy that it proposes is not the self-interest
of any individual, but rather a (hypothetical) contract that promotes or
reconciles the interests of all concerned. Thus the theory appeals not
only to self-interest, but also to a due concern for the interests of one's
fellows. It seeks to balance the equally legitimate interests of all. This
fact, no doubt, accounts for the continuing popularity of the idea in present-day
political discourse; and also makes intelligible the fact that the modern
philosophical revival of contract theory has been, above all, as a theory
of justice.
CONTRACT THEORY DOESN'T STRESS HUMAN
SELFISHNESS
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.119.
Reformulation of social contract
theory in the hypothetical mode alters the picture in details, but not
in essentials. It is true that there can then no longer be any reliance
on the moral obligation to keep promises; rather, the obligation postulated
is to accept, support or obey institutions that are in one's interest,
as well as in the interests of all others affected. Thus interpreted, Hobbes's
argument is that there is an (almost absolute) moral obligation to obey
the sovereign, because it is on balance in one's interest (and in everyone's
interest) to be ruled by a nearly absolute sovereign: the argument is not
that obedience to the sovereign is always in one's own selfish interest,
which would be manifestly absurd. Admittedly, Hobbes's version of social
contract theory is problematic, precisely because he does appear to postulate
(though this has been disputed by some commentators) that all human action
is selfishly motivated. It then becomes dubious whether such purely selfish
individuals are capable of adhering to the moral obligation that Hobbes
prescribes to them (cf. Gauthier above). But the important point is that
Hobbes is in this respect untypical of social contract theory; that, indeed,
the postulate of purely selfish human nature, far from being congruent
with contract theory, threatens to undermine it.
POLITICAL OBLIGATION NOT NEEDED;
MORAL OBLIGATION IS SUFFICIENT
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.151-2.
The fact that both contractarians
and anticontractarians fail to justify political obligation (understood
as a self-assumed obligation) is nothing new; the anarchists have argued
similarly for a long time. But from this conclusion nothing really dramatic
follows. From the fact that we generally do not have political obligations,
it does not follow that we can disobey the laws of the land as we please.
Most of the time there are legitimate moral reasons for compliance. If
this is true, we ought to respect the law, not because we have a political
obligation to do so but because there are important moral reasons for doing
so. As free moral agents (autonomous persons), we have natural obligations
that must be taken into consideration before we obey or disobey any law
or regulation. |
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS FLAWED
CONTRACTARIANISM IS OVERLY ABSTRACT
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.153.
To sum up, the critics of contractarianism
have successfully demonstrated the futile abstractness of this approach
to political philosophy. From a hypothetical contract in a hypothetical
situation one can only derive hypothetical obligations. Hypothetical obligations
are not actual obligations, and a hypothetical contract is not a real contract.
If the main idea behind the social contract tradition is to justify political
authority, then contractarianism fails in achieving this objective. If
political authority can indeed be morally justified, it must be justified
either on utilitarian grounds, or on concrete considerations of justice,
or on both, but not on hypothetical considerations.
SOCIAL CONTRACT PRODUCES AN ARROGANT
ABSTRACT IDEA OF JUSTICE
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.61-2.
Nevertheless, it does not take
much critical imagination to realize how much the subject of justice has
been distorted and overidealized by these philosophers. The very idea of
founding a society (much less society as such) is so arrogant, so abstract
and so distracting from the actual problems of justice and injustice that
we should from the start be extremely suspicious of any theory of justice
that starts by suggesting not a better but a different society or begins
by pretending that society is unnatural and was formed by the rational
agreement (for whatever reasons) of presocial individuals, as if we could,
even in theory, momentarily retreat to that original position and renegotiate
the basic terms under which we live.
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS MYTHICAL
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.633.
The social contract, in the sense
required, is mythical even when, at some former period, there actually
was a contract creating the government in question. The United States is
a case in point. At the time when the Constitution was adopted, men had
liberty of choice. Even then, many voted against it, and were therefore
not parties to the contract. They could, of course, have left the country,
and by remaining were deemed to have become bound by a contract to which
they had not assented. But in practice it is usually difficult to leave
one's country. And in the case of men born after the adoption of the Constitution
their consent is even more shadowy.
THE CONTRACT DOESN'T JUSTIFY OBEDIENCE
TO THE STATE
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.143-4.
And, finally, I will question whether
contractarianism in any of its forms, can provide an adequate answer to
a third important question: Is the concept of the social contract necessary
or sufficient to justify a general prima facie moral obligation to obey
the state and its institutions? We may agree that we have a moral obligation
to promote a "just" government (what Rawls understands as a natural duly
of justice) but consistently deny that we have a political obligation (understood
as a self-assumed obligation) to obey all or most of the laws emanating
from such an authority.
MOST PEOPLE NEVER CONSENT TO THE
STATE'S AUTHORITY
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.150.
If my analysis of political obligation
is correct, then the large majority of people are not bound by it, although
they may be bound to their community by their patriotic sentiments and
their natural moral obligations. Most people are born as members of a particular
political society (state), and they are never or hardly ever asked whether
they voluntarily accept the state's authority and its benefits. Even those
who argue that political obligations are generated through the "principle
of fair play" fail in their quest for justification.
RECEIVING BENEFITS FROM SOCIETY
DOESN'T MANDATE OBEDIENCE
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.148.
But as I have already argued, a
promise as such can never be sufficient to generate a general prima facie
obligation to obey the law. And although it is true, generally speaking,
that citizens have acquired benefits by residing in a particular political
community, it is also true that, if they have been good citizens, they
have provided benefits to others by contributing to the well-being and
stability of the community. This is not a one-way relationship in which
one of the parties involved receives benefits at the expense of others.
Instead this is a quid pro quo situation in which all parties benefit to
some degree.
PEOPLE ARE ONLY OBLIGATED TO OBEY
JUST LAWS
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.147-8.
We need to keep in mind that a
naturalized citizen is, before anything else, an autonomous person and,
as such, is only morally obligated to obey just laws. It might be argued
that naturalized citizens acquire a prima facie political obligation to
obey the law of the land by virtue of their oath of citizenship. However,
even in the case of naturalized citizens it is not clear that this oath
is always performed voluntarily, since, for example, there might be social
pressures compelling them to become citizens. And even if there were no
social or any other kind of pressure, the oath of citizenship, from the
perspective of moral agency, does not have any significant moral weight.
We simply promise faithful allegiance to those rules and regulations that
are morally right; but one ought to respect these rules and regulations
by virtue of their being morally right, regardless of what one has promised.
Thus it follows that an oath of allegiance is virtually otiose from a moral
point of view, although important from a legal perspective.
HYPOTHETICAL CONTRACTS LACK BINDING
FORCE
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.60.
Of course, virtually every author
on the subject insists that there was in fact no such state of nature.
(Rousseau boldly announces, "Let's begin by ignoring all the facts.") But
these authors clearly do believe that, prehistory aside, we are independent,
autonomous beings by nature, concerned primarily with calculating our own
interests, living together only grudgingly. So, too, the authors who defend
the idea of a social contract virtually never suggest that there was, in
fact, such a historical agreement. But, then, it is not easy to understand
what sort of binding force this fiction is supposed to have on us.
IDEAL CONTRACTS ARE CIRCULAR
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.94.
The distinction between a hypothetical
and an ideal social contract is an important one, and in one respect the
former seems to be much the more valid concept of the two (we are now assuming
that the idea of an actual social contract is discredited). To invoke an
ideal contract is to appeal to what individuals, ideally, ought to agree
to, or what they would agree to if they were ideally moral beings. As a
way of arguing for or against particular political institutions, this seems
needlessly circuitous. In brief, morally good beings would agree to morally
good institutions, and whatever arguments might be deployed to show that
institutions are such that morally good beings would (or would not) agree
to them, could be deployed directly in defense of (or against) the institutions
themselves, without reference to agreement, contract, or consent.
HYPOTHETICAL CONTRACT ARGUMENTS
ARE OVERLY SPECULATIVE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.94-5.
The notion of deriving political
obligation from what men would agree to in a state of nature, while avoiding
some of the difficulties of the actual and the ideal social contracts,
still faces some old problems as well as some new ones. One problem is
that such an argument is inevitably speculative (though no more so than
arguments about supposedly actual contracts of which no record remains).
Both this hypothetical contract, and the supposedly actual but unrecorded
contract, in effect depend on postulates about human nature- a universal
human nature which motivates a universal contract and so generates universal
principles of political obligation. Arguments on this score are liable
to be somewhat treacherous.
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT ISN'T NEEDED
FOR A THEORY OF RIGHTS
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.143.
A second important question can
now be taken up briefly. Is the concept of the social contract necessary
for the development of a general theory of rights that accounts for natural
or moral rights? The answer is clear. The idea of the social contract is
superfluous to our understanding of natural or moral rights. This can be
seen clearly in Locke's political philosophy. Locke, in his Second Treatise
of Government, develops his theory of natural rights before even mentioning
any sort of contract. Natural rights, according to Locke, are rights we
possess by virtue of our nature. Thus a contract can neither confer these
rights (natural or moral) nor take them away. If so, then we can develop
a general theory of rights or talk meaningfully about rights without any
reference to the social contract.
NATURAL RIGHTS AND THE SOCIAL CONTRACT
ARE LOGICALLY NOT THE SAME THING
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.143.
The concept of the social contract
is neither necessary nor sufficient to explain natural or moral rights.
The fact that most advocates of contractarianism also talk about natural
rights is a matter of a contingent historical situation rather than the
result of any logical connection between the social contract and natural
rights. These are two radically different concepts. Consequently, we can
talk about one without necessarily talking about the other. The notion
of natural rights is a more fundamental notion than that of a social contract.
In fact, most contractarian philosophers use the metaphor of the social
contract partly as a way of explaining why we ought to protect natural
rights. But if natural rights are rights we possess by virtue of our nature,
then we ought to respect them regardless of any contract or agreement.
Such respect is necessary for the development of our moral personality
as well as for our personal integrity.
SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY IS ANTHROPOLOGICALLY
NAIVE
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.633.
The theory that government was
created by a contract is, of course, pre-evolutionary. Government, like
measles and whooping-cough, must have grown up gradually, though, like
them, it could be introduced suddenly into new regions such as the South
Sea Islands. Before men had studied anthropology they had no idea of the
psychological mechanisms involved in the beginnings of government, or of
the fantastic reasons which lead men to adopt institutions and customs
that subsequently prove useful. But as a legal fiction, to justify government,
the theory of the social contract has some measure of truth.
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT IS A HISTORICAL
ABSURDITY
DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, PROFESSORS
OF POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS,
1994, P.16.
J. K. Bluntschli, for example,
writing during the mid-nineteenth century, criticized Pufendorf, Locke
and Kant (to a lesser extent) for failing to see that the will of the person
of the state was not composed of the wills of each individual. For Bluntschli
the social contract was both historically and logically absurd. There was
no evidence of any such historical event, and a political contract, dealing
as it did not with private but public goods, required the prior existence
of the community whose common good it aimed to promote. He argued that
the state was a developing maturing 'moral and spiritual organism' with
'a personality which, having spirit and body, possesses and manifests a
will of its own'.
EVOLUTIONARY THEORY DENIES THE SOCIAL
CONTRACT MODEL
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.130.
One dominant metaphor in recent
evolutionary theory is the game, which does not, of course, suggest that
the animals that are fighting for their survival are having fun. But it
is a metaphor that has the virtue of embracing both competition and cooperation
within a framework in which the integrity of the group is presupposed.
In this, it is both slightly similar to and dramatically different from
that "state of nature" model that defines so many theories of justice from
Hobbes and Rousseau to Rawls.
THERE'S NO EVIDENCE ON THE EVOLUTION
OF A CONTRACT
JEREMY WALDRON, PROFESSOR OF LAW,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO
RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.55.
As if this were not enough, there
is a further difficulty with the historical plausibility of the contractarian
account. Not only is there evidence that political society evolved in a
non-contractarian way, there is also none of the sort of evidence we should
expect to find if contractarian events had been involved in its development.
The point is stated clearly by David Hume: It is strange, that an act of
mind, which every individual is supposed to have formed, and after he came
to the use of reason too, otherwise it could have no authority; that this
act, I say, should be so much unknown to all of them, that, over the face
of the whole earth, there scarcely remain any traces or memory of it.
THE HISTORICAL CRITICISM OF THE
CONTRACT IS RIGHT
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.88.
As an account of the history of
states, then, even the Althusian version of the contract theory, and the
ancient notion of a contract between people and ruler which it incorporates,
are highly imperfect. And the problems on this score are much greater for
the 'classical' version of contract theory, which portrays the state as
a creation of numerous individuals (or heads of families) contracting together,
and supposes that subsequent generations of citizens adhere, one by one,
to the original contract. Here the scepticism of Filmer and Hume as to
the reality of such contracts seems highly persuasive. In sum, our answer
to question (1) must be, Yes, the critics are right.
FICTITIOUS CONTRACT UNDERMINES CLASSICAL
SOCIAL CONTRACT
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.89-90.
ln this case the entire notion
that government is founded on contract is fictitious; a fact which is indeed
fatal to contract theory in its standard form, that is, from Manegold to
Locke. It is worth repeating why this is so. The theory of social contract,
in its standard form, holds that the political obligation of peoples and
individuals, and the limits of that obligation, derive from undertakings
that they (and perhaps also their rulers have voluntarily given. If they
have not in fact, given any such undertakings, no conclusion about their
obligations can be derived in this way.
EVEN MOST PLAUSIBLE HISTORICAL THEORY
OF THE CONTRACT HAS FLAWS
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.87-8.
Perhaps the most plausible, as
a strictly historical account, is that of Althusius, which envisages the
union of individuals into families and other private associations, of private
associations into lesser public associations and of the lesser public associations
into commonwealths. Althusius also incorporated the ancient concept of
a contract between the people and its (future) ruler, both at the institution
of the state and at the election of a new prince; and this element is not
only plausible, but is even a reasonable interpretation of the constitution
of some medieval European kingdoms. Nevertheless, as history, the Althusian
theory suffers from several defects. First, the plausibility of the contract
between people and ruler depends on one's willingness to allow that the
people can act through representatives, and its accuracy as history requires
that certain magnates, not delegated by the people, may be considered as
occupying this representative role. Here, it is hard not to side with Filmer
in rejecting such a notion. Second, it would not be sufficient if the constitutions
of some particular medieval states did indeed incorporate a contract between
ruler and people - for contract theory claims to be a general theory of
legitimate government. And third, a degree of plausibility is not the same
thing as actual historicity, and while the Althusian sequence of events
may not be too implausible, this is not to say that it actually occurred
(the sequence in its Aristotelian version, as a natural progression, may
well seem the more plausible of the two).
PEOPLE IN STATE OF NATURE LACK CONTRACT
SOPHISTICATION
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.56.
But we are evidently very clever
at figuring out what is good for us, and we are capable--according to the
theory--of getting together and negotiating our personal and mutual interests
and hammering out a contract that spells out the terms of our agreement
and provides incentives and sanctions for our compliance. That is asking
an awful lot from a first gathering of presumably primitive creatures who
probably know very little about one another and certainly do not share
even the beginnings of a language, much less the complicated legal concepts
that are essential to contracts. Pre-social humanity was both remarkably
sophisticated and, it seems, only grudgingly cooperative. The state of
nature is one of those grand ancient myths with which people have always
proved to themselves both how clever we have always been and how much better
off we are now.
AMERICA DOESN'T PROVE THE VIABILITY
OF PRIMITIVE SOCIAL CONTRACT
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.57.
We do, of course, have an inspiring
example of a society actually formed by virtue of such a contract, and
that is our own. The "contract" is our Constitution. But, needless to say,
it was not presocial savages who gathered together in Philadelphia two
centuries ago. They were well-trained, highly skilled, and well-read lawyers
and statesmen. (Some of their favorite reading was precisely the philosophical
literature on the social contract.) And the society they "founded" was
by no means society as such, society built up from the ground up, but a
considerably improved version of the Western European (especially British)
type of society that already existed in the colonies, in which property
was already established, in which local laws against theft and murder and
a thousand other crimes were already in place together with a system of
punishment to enforce them. The social contract metaphor, on the other
hand, presumes an outrageous pretension, that we can build society from
scratch, and may have actually done so. The myth of the state of nature
is an analysis of the raw ingredients we used to do this.
ORIGINAL LEGITIMACY DOESN'T ASSURE
CONTINUING LEGITIMACY
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.89.
For example, it is widely held
that the federal constitution of the United States of America is legitimate
today, because it was agreed by legitimate procedures involving the representatives
of the people involved in 1787 (and in later years, when other states acceded).
No one would dream of questioning the legitimacy of the American government's
authority on the grounds that later generations of citizens have been given
no opportunity to consent to it; the (indirect) consent of the first generation
is acknowledged to be sufficient, as well as (many would hold) necessary
for this legitimacy. It takes the penetration of a Hume to show that this
kind of thinking is sloppy and untenable.
CONTRACTARIANS CAN'T AGREE ON CONSISTENT
FORM FOR IDEAL STATE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.95-6.
What is essentially the same problem
can be put in a different way. It is perhaps not hard to show that a given
form of state is more advantageous for everyone than no state at all (though
even this the anarchists, by definition, would deny). But there may be
many such forms of state. How, then, can this mode of reasoning show which
is the legitimate or best form of state, as contract theory down the centuries
has sought to do? Just this difficulty accounts for the huge variety of
state forms and constitutions that have been defended by different contract
theorists - a variety which has been exemplified in the pages of this book,
and is symptomatic of the problematic character of the contractarian idea.
SOCIAL DIVERSITY MAKES CONTRACTUALISM
PROBLEMATIC
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.105.
Meanwhile, let us remind ourselves
of the real reason why man's social nature raises problems for contract
theory. That theory standardly rests on an assumption of a universal human
nature, from which a universal contract can be derived. Yet if man is essentially
social, and human societies are historically and culturally diverse then
human nature will appear to be radically diverse also. The model of man
used in social contract theory thus risks, as was said above, being not
only unreal but arbitrary - what is taken to be human nature may be only
one of innumerable possible human natures, and the temptation is great
to construct the model just in such a way as to generate the desired conclusions.
CONTRACTUALISM CAN'T DEAL WITH MULTIPLE
VIEWS OF GOOD
DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, PROFESSORS
OF POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS,
1994, P.26.
Any political authority which adopts
strict neutrality towards the goods that individuals pursue is in danger
of seeing the diversity of a plural culture disappear in the face of mass
opinion. If, on the other hand, the state adopts a stance of protecting
important components of a society's culture then it must necessarily abandon
a strict impartiality between individual's choices and forms of life and
assert grounds for preferring some ways of life above others. This cannot
be done within the terms of contract arguments. Thus critics such as Taylor
argue that even political liberalism needs more than the underpinnings
of a neutralist contractarianism.
SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY FALSELY ASSUMES
INNATE SELFISHNESS
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.71.
Underlying the idea of a social
contract to protect us from one another is the uncritical and inadequate
notion that we are all basically selfish and competitive. It is as if our
selfish desires occur naturally, quite apart from ethics or society, but
our sense of justice is not natural at all. Against this, Plato argues
that justice cannot be just a social convention but must be found in the
nature of the soul of the agent. This means that selfishness cannot be
so simply opposed to justice, and justice must be understood in terms of
what kind of people we are and should be. Justice does not depend on a
contract or on anyone's sense of obligation. Indeed, the ancient Greeks
did not even have our overly contractual notion of "obligation." It is
simply not true that all of us are basically selfish creatures who need
contractual obligations to keep us in line. Indeed, holding simultaneously
to the antagonistic concepts of "selfishness" and "obligation" makes any
adequate conception of justice impossible.
HUMANS HAVE ALWAYS BEEN SOCIAL BEINGS
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.151.
From the earliest transitional,
quasi-human beings, Australopithecus and onward, we have been social animals
with social instincts, born into and living in already established groups.
We would certainly not have survived otherwise. A group of cooperating
men can kill a saber-toothed tiger which could easily kill any of them
individually. Our attachments to and dependency on not only our parents
but our peers and our neighbors precede by hundreds of thousands of years
(or more) our willingness to engage in negotiations and make explicit agreements.
Our compassion and affection for one another, however threatened by mutual
distrust, envy, and jealousy, and our sense of sociability and mutual cooperation,
however threatened by ambition and deviousness, have a far more solid and
unshakable basis than a possibly nonbinding rational agreement.
GENERAL SUSPICION OF SOCIETY IS
SELF-DESTRUCTIVE
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.151.
It is true that we are often suspicious
of governments and rightly distrustful of the state in any form, but it
is ultimately self-defeating if not self-destructive to be distrustful
of society per se, even if in any particular case it makes perfectly good
sense to be reflective and reform-minded about the character of one's own
group or culture. We are social creatures, and the illusion of the self
against society is no more than one of the dominant but very peculiar rules
of reciprocal altruism in a society that has grown much too large and complex
to have any simple rules.
HUMANS ARE UNLIKE THE WAY CONTRACT
THEORISTS DESCRIBE THEM
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.150-1.
We never were, never could have
been, and never wanted to be the independent, autonomous creatures that
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, expressing his own paranoia, fantasized about. We
never were the selfish, nasty, brutal beings that Thomas Hobbes posited.
We never were and never could be the purely rational beings that John Rawls
envisions. We are not in any sense the independent and self-interested
creatures that smart philosophy and bad biology make us out to be.
NATURAL SOCIABILITY DISPROVES THE
CONTRACT
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.149-50.
The prominent foundation of many
current theories of justice--the so-called "social contract" and the contrasting
"state of nature"--should be reconsidered within the context of this biological
picture. It is all well and good to insist that this picture is merely
hypothetical and in fact a thought-experiment to bring to light the rationality
of certain social arrangements. But the fact is that certain deep assumptions
are being made about justice and about human nature before that thought
experiment even begins. One need not accept the hard determinist's view
of the world and insist that what we are by nature determines what we must
be in order to recognize that we are by nature certain sorts of creatures.
We are, like wolves and chimps, products not just of our genes but of the
conditions in which we find ourselves, which are, first and foremost, social
conditions. That is where the state of nature theorists go so wrong; there
is no individual in the state of nature, no war of all against all except
in a few paranoid or polemical minds and in the self-justifying rhetoric
of some Wall Street hostile takeover moguls. It is not just the fact of
our sociability that is in question here; it is our natural constitution
as social animals, in which reason may play a major role, but only because
it becomes instrumental in the management of the increasing complications
of our natural reciprocity.
HUMAN NATURE IS MEANINGLESS OUTSIDE
A SOCIAL CONTEXT
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.62.
It is against the twin mythology
of a "state of nature," according to which we are all independent, autonomous
beings, and a "social contract," according to which we are rational, mutually
committed individuals, that my argument in this book is directed. My thesis
is that it makes no sense to talk about human nature--whether as pure rationality
or productivity and possessiveness--apart from those features that we cultivate
and acquire in society, and at the same time that there is no need to bring
in rationality as a corrective for an essentially selfish human nature.
Our affiliations in society and with each other are not rational or a matter
of self-interested calculation but a product of natural feelings and affections.
It is selfishness and not society that is unnatural, and justice should
not be conceived as a rational corrective to our natural human emotions.
SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY DENIES OUR
ESSENTIALLY SOCIAL NATURE
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.54-5.
One such grand theory rules our
thinking today. It provides the starting point for our thinking and the
ground rules for our conceptions and discussions about justice. It has
all the intellectual elegance that the smartest philosophers of modern
times have contributed, and it has all of the appeal that our most deeply
felt political opinions can provide. It is a theory that has become labyrinthine
in its development but is almost childishly simple in its basic conception.
It is the theory that has come to be known as the theory of "the social
contract," and it encompasses not only a theory of justice but a theory
of human nature and our basic emotions and motivation as well. In its most
basic formulation, it is the view that justice--and the very existence
of society as such--is created and justified by the fact that we all agree
to its principles because they ultimately serve each of our best interests.
In many versions of the theory, justice becomes a matter of reason whose
purpose is to counter and control the unruly and usually selfish dictates
of our natural passions. I want to argue that such theories rather reduce
reason to the mere calculation of self-interest and ignore or even deny
our emotional and essentially social nature.
THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT ISN'T GROUNDED
ON REASON
DAVID HUME, "OF THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT,"
IN HUME'S ETHICAL WRITINGS, ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, ED., 1748, P.258-9.
Were you to preach, in most parts
of the world, that political connexions are founded altogether on voluntary
consent or a mutual promise, the magistrate would soon imprison you, as
seditious, for loosening the ties of obedience; if your friends did not
before shut you up as delirious, for advancing such absurdities. It is
strange, that an act of the mind, which every individual is supposed to
have formed, and after he came to the use of reason too, otherwise it could
have no authority; that this act, I say, should be so much unknown to all
of them, that, over the face of the whole earth, there scarcely remain
any traces or memory of it.
THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT LACKS AUTHORITY
DAVID HUME, "OF THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT,"
IN HUME'S ETHICAL WRITINGS, ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, ED., 1748, P.259.
But the contract, on which government
is founded, is said to be the original contract; and consequently may be
supposed too old to fall under the knowledge of the present generation.
If the agreement, by which savage men first associated and conjoined their
force, be here meant, this is acknowledged to be real; but being so ancient,
and being obliterated by a thousand changes of government and princes,
it cannot now be supposed to retain any authority. If we would say any
thing to the purpose, we must assert, that every particular government,
which is lawful, and which imposes any duty of allegiance on the subject,
was, at first, founded on consent and a voluntary compact. But besides
that this supposes the consent of the fathers to bind the children, even
to the most remote generations, (which republican writers will never allow)
besides this, I say, it is not justified by history or experience, in any
age or country of the world.
THE LACK OF A CONTRACT CONCEPT IN
ANTIQUITY PROVES IT INVALID
DAVID HUME, "OF THE ORIGINAL CONTRACT,"
IN HUME'S ETHICAL WRITINGS, ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, ED., 1748, P.273.
The only passage I meet with in
antiquity, where the obligation of obedience to government is ascribed
to a promise, is in Plato's Crito: where Socrates refuses to escape from
prison, because he had tacitly promised to obey the laws. Thus he builds
a tory consequence of passive obedience, on a whig foundation of the original
contract. New discoveries are not to be expected in these matters. If scarce
any man, till very lately, ever imagined that government was founded on
compact, it is certain that it cannot, in general, have any such foundation.
FOR HUME, EXPERIENCE DENIES THE
CONTRACT
DARIO CASTIGLIONE, LECTURER IN
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF EXETER, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS,
DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.106-7.
According to Hume, the consensual
theory of political obligation makes nonsense of people's own perception
of the relationships in which they engage. What Hume referred to as the
'authority' of received opinion was in his view a forceful argument, not
so much because these opinions matter in the courts of reason or philosophy,
but because in common life received opinion is part of the very reality
which needs to be explained. The apparent prescriptive value which Hume
attributes to experience is not absolute, in the sense that there is no
fixed record of experience which ought to be applied to our system of values;
on the other hand, experience represents the limit of general philosophizing,
because philosophy cannot overturn human nature. This kind of argument
was of extreme importance in Hume's political philosophy, since he maintained
that all sciences dealing with matters of fact - politics being one of
them - are entirely based on experience. So, in rejecting experience, contract
theorists were doing bad metaphysics. Moreover, by failing to recognize
that some form of political obligation was at work in all of those instances
where the consent of the people played no part - and, of course, these
were by far the greatest number - they were unwittingly maintaining that
political experience is only the product of unreason.
LACK OF GENERAL PUBLIC AWARENESS
REFUTES THE CONTRACT
DARIO CASTIGLIONE, LECTURER IN
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF EXETER, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS,
DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.110.
According to Hume, people's lack
of awareness, particularly in the case of posterity, cuts at the root of
consensual theories of political obligation because it amounts to a clear
proof that no act of the will has taken place: 'A tacit promise is, where
the will is signified by other more diffuse signs than those of speech;
but a will there must certainly be in the case, and that can never escape
the person's notice, who exerted it, however silent or tacit'. Since a
necessary condition for an act of the will is to be known to the person
who exercises it, according to Hume, people's lack of awareness of having
engaged in a covenant is conclusive proof that such an unknown promise
is no promise at all.
THE GOOD LIFE ISN'T PRIOR TO OR
OPPOSED TO SOCIETY
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.152.
We are bound by our biology, our
culture, our circumstances, and our characters. It is no argument against
freedom and autonomy to say, against so much of recent philosophy and ideology,
that freedom and autonomy have their limits. Nor is it an argument or excuse
for excessive government to insist that society is prior to individual
rights. The Greeks had it right: to live a good life, live in a good society.
The idea that the good life is something prior to and opposed to society
as such is a bit of insanity that only the anonymity and agoraphobia of
modern urban society could inspire.
CONTRACTUALISM CAN ALIENATE US FROM
OUR EMOTIONS
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.31-3.
Throughout this book, I will have
much to say about this hardly flattering model of "natural" humanity and
the formation of society by way of a mutually agreed-upon contract. It
is this model, in its many variations, that forms the foundation for just
about every theory of justice now in the books or on the drawing boards.
For now, however, I just want to point out the viciousness of the dichotomy
it presumes--our natural inclinations (most of them selfish) on the one
side, our social and contractual obligations and expectations on the other.
It is, to begin with, a dubious distinction--between inclinations and obligations,
between our natural existence and our social existence, between the natural
disposition of our feelings and the rationality that allows us to form
society and then live in it. But it is a vicious dichotomy, emotion versus
reason, and these two classic metaphors-- the "state of nature" and "the
social contract"--have a dangerous appeal for us. They make us distance
ourselves from our emotions (falsely conceived of as "natural" and presocial)
and encourage us to entertain the appealing fiction that we live in society
by voluntary choice rather than just because we happened to be born and
raised here. The metaphors suggest a convenient way of defusing unwanted
obligations not of our own choosing and defending the most unreasonable
expectations as "rights." They provide a flattering way of fooling ourselves
into thinking that we are above nature and smarter than our emotions, rational
creatures who have taken our existence--and especially our social existence--into
our own hands.
SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORY IS BASED
ON HATRED AND RESENTMENT
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.61.
I think we should be extremely
suspicious of all of those social thinkers who suggest that a theory of
justice is an attempt to establish justice by creating society anew. Beginning
with Plato's Republic, philosophers have developed theories of justice
that try to replace their own society with another, better one, and the
social contract is but the latest intellectual device for doing this. But
the attempt to replace one's society suggests that the motivation behind
these various theories of justice, however couched in the language of rationality,
consists largely of such emotions as contempt and resentment. Could it
even be that some of the quest is simple self-hatred, as in Jean-Jacques
Rousseau's attempt to design a society that would no longer have room for
people like himself?
CONTRACTUALISM IS UNDERMINED BY
THE REQUIREMENT FOR UNANIMITY
DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, PROFESSORS
OF POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS,
1994, P.18-9.
Filmer went to great pains to expose
the absurdity of contractarian arguments, and it is this aspect of his
thought that is widely considered the most penetrating. If people are naturally
free and equal, he argues, and if God granted property in common, then
it would require a unanimous agreement to take anything out of the common
stock, or to institute an authority over them, a condition, in his view,
that was simply impractical.
POLITICAL SOCIETY ISN'T A CLUB WE
VOLUNTARILY JOIN
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.151.
Yet political society is not like
a club that we voluntarily join, voluntarily accepting the obligations
attached to our membership. Political society is more like a family: we
are born into it without any choice. We use the benefits provided by political
society without voluntarily accepting them in any real sense; we just take
these benefits for granted.
POLITICAL COMMITMENTS DON'T JUSTIFY
IMMORAL ACTS
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.147.
If we agree that political obligation
should be understood as a self-assumed obligation that we voluntarily impose
on ourselves, as when we promise to do something, or when we enter into
a contractual relation, then most people in society do not appear to be
bound by this political obligation. Even naturalized citizens do not promise
to obey the state and its institutions unconditionally, since they cannot
give up moral agency on demand, as if selling themselves into slavery.
One should only consent to do that which is morally acceptable. Individuals
can always assent to do something morally wrong, but it does not follow
that they are morally obliged to do so. On the contrary, once we recognize
that we have promised to do something immoral, we ought not to fulfill
our promise.
ECOLOGICAL SCARCITY UNDERMINES SOCIAL
CONTRACT THEORY
WILLIAM OPHULS, FORMER PROFESSOR
OF POLITICAL SCIENCE, NORTHWESTERN AND A. STEPHEN BOYAN, PROFESSOR OF POLITICAL
SCIENCE, UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND, ECOLOGY AND THE POLITICS OF SCARCITY REVISITED,
1992, P.216.
Ecological scarcity thus forces
us to confront once again, perhaps in a particularly acute form, the hard
realities and cruel dilemmas of classical politics, from which four centuries
of abnormal abundance have shielded us. As a result, we shall have to reexamine
fundamental political questions in the light of ecology and construct a
new steady-state paradigm of politics based on ecological premises instead
of on the individualistic, hedonistic, materialistic, and anthropocentric
premises of bourgeois "social contract" theory (see Box 22). The alternative
is to let the shape of the steady-state paradigm be decided for us by accepting
the outcome of current trends toward technocracy.
LIBERAL DEMOCRACY CAN'T COPE WITH
ECOLOGICAL SCARCITY
WILLIAM OPHULS, FORMER PROFESSOR
OF POLITICAL SCIENCE, NORTHWESTERN AND A. STEPHEN BOYAN, PROFESSOR OF POLITICAL
SCIENCE, UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND, ECOLOGY AND THE POLITICS OF SCARCITY REVISITED,
1992, P.3.
This book argues, to the contrary,
that the external reality of ecological scarcity has cut the ground out
from under our own political system, making merely reformist policies of
ecological management all but useless. At best, reforms can postpone the
inevitable for a few decades at the probable cost of increasing the severity
of the eventual day of reckoning. In brief, liberal democracy as we know
it-that is, our theory or "paradigm'' of politics (see Box 1)-is doomed
by ecological scarcity; we need a completely new political philosophy and
set of political institutions. Moreover, it appears that the basic principles
of modern industrial civilization are also incompatible with ecological
scarcity and that the whole ideology of modernity growing out of the Enlightenment,
especially such central tenets as individualism, may no longer be viable. |
HOBBES WAS RIGHT!
GOVERNMENT IS INITIATED BY AN ORIGINAL
CONTRACT
THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN (PENGUIN
EDITION), 1651, P.228-9.
A Common-wealth is said to be Instituted,
when a Multitude of men do Agree, and Covenant, every one, with every one,
that to whatsoever Man, or Assembly of Men, shall be given by the major
part, the Right to Present the Person of them all, (that is to say, to
be their Representative ;) every one, as well he that Voted for it, as
he that Voted against it, shall Authorise all the Actions and Judgments,
of that Man, or Assembly of men, in the same manner, as if they were his
own, to the end, to live peaceably amongst themselves, and be protected
against other men.
THE HOBBESIAN CONTRACT PROVIDES
THE BASIS FOR LEGITIMATE POLITIC
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.10-1.
The elements of the Hobbesian theory
are, briefly, these. Men are exhibited in what has come to be called the
state of nature (Hobbes himself in the Leviathan calls it the estate of
nature, or the natural condition of mankind). This is a definition of what
men and their relations are naturally like, that is, in the absence of
any deliberately contrived institutions. Contrary to the Aristotelian view,
it is a non-political condition, devoid of any political authority. In
it all men have a natural right of liberty, but it is none the less a patently
unsatisfactory state of affairs, and reason clearly demonstrates the preferability
of political society under an effective authority. This must therefore
be established by general agreement, by what Hobbes calls a covenant of
every man with every man, or, in other words, a social contract. This contract
is, then, the basis of legitimate political authority and of political
obligation. In making it and abiding by it, Hobbes says, men obey the law
of nature, the true moral law. Hobbes' theory thus combines with the idea
of social contract the ideas of state of nature, natural right, and law
of nature.
HOBBES WAS RIGHT - LACK OF FORMALIZED
RULES MEANS ANARCHY
JAMES BUCHANAN, PROFESSOR OF ECONOMICS,
VIRGINIA POLYTECHNIC, ANARCHISM, J. ROWLAND PENNOCK AND JOHN CHAPMAN, EDS.,
1978, P.39.
The only alternative seems to be
found in the distribution of limits on individuals, spheres of action that
would be found in the total absence of formalized rules, that is, in genuine
Hobbesian anarchy. In this setting, some "equilibrium," some sustainable
distribution of allowable activities would emerge. This distribution would
depend on the relative strengths and abilities of persons to acquire and
to maintain desirable goods and assets. The "law of the jungle" would be
controlling, and no serious effort could be made to attribute moral legitimacy
to the relative holdings of persons.
POLITICAL OBLIGATION IS OWED TO
WHOEVER HAS POWER
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.56.
All obligation of obedience, indeed,
depends on the sovereign's power, and when he loses it, he loses his authority
also. Our obligation is always to the ruler with effective power (on which
peace depends). A sovereign who acquires power by force, possibly by overthrowing
a previous government, has exactly the same authority, and is owed the
same obligation, as a sovereign established by an original or other contract
(HL, 272,252). The rationale of his authority is exactly the same, and
the fact that he may have acquired his power by illegal and unjust means
- means which Hobbes unreservedly condemns - is irrelevant. It was doctrines
such as these that permitted Hobbes to rally to Cromwell in 1651, and made
him so suspect to royalists and political traditionalists generally.
REASON REQUIRES SACRIFICING THE
RIGHT TO AGGRESS
THOMAS HOBBES, LEVIATHAN (PENGUIN
EDITION), 1651, P.190.
From this Fundamentall Law of Nature,
by which men are commanded to endeavour Peace, is derived this second Law;
That a man be willing, when others are so too, as farre-forth, as for Peace,
and (65) defence of himselfe he shall think it necessary, to lay down this
right to all things; and be contented with so much liberty against other
men, as he would allow other men against himselfe. For as long as every
man holdeth this Right, of doing any thing he liketh; so long are all men
in the condition of Warre. But if other men will not lay down their Right,
as well as he; then there is no Reason for any one, to devest himselfe
of his: For that were to expose himselfe to Prey, (which no man is bound
to) rather than to dispose himselfe to Peace.
HOBBES' THEORY WAS A MAJOR ADVANCE
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.556.
The merits of Hobbes appear most
clearly when he is contrasted with earlier political theorists. He is completely
free from superstition; he does not argue from what happened to Adam and
Eve at the of the Fall. He is clear and logical; his ethics, right or wrong,
is completely intelligible, and does not involve the use of any dubious
concepts. Apart from Machiavelli, who is much more limited, he is the first
really modern writer on political theory. Where he is wrong, he is wrong
from over-simplification, not because the basis of his thought is unreal
and fantastic. For this reason, he is still worth refuting.
HOBBES THEORY WAS ORIGINAL AND IMPRESSIVE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.46.
Hobbes's version of the social
contract theory is philosophically the most impressive of all. It is also
the most innovative, both philosophically and politically. Politically,
it is highly unusual in that it used contract theory to defend and uphold
the authority of rulers, indeed a (nearly) absolute authority. Of all the
many previous contract theorists we have surveyed, only one - Engelbert
of Volkersdorf - was also a supporter of secular authority (that of the
Emperor), and even he can hardly he said to have used contract theory much
or very convincingly to that end. Philosophically, Hobbes was just as original,
and in too many ways to yield to easy summary. |
HOBBES WAS WRONG!
HOBBES MISUNDERSTOOD HUMAN NATURE
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.106.
But, of course, it was not stones,
volcanoes, and monsoons that Hobbes had in mind. He was referring to people,
or whatever creatures immediately preceded people, in the so-called "state
of nature," humanity before it was socialized and civilized, humanity not
yet fully human. His thesis was that there is nothing in either nature
or human nature that makes us just, except for the conventions and laws
of society. In nature, as opposed to society, there is only unceasing competition
and brutality, "red in tooth and claw." But I want to argue that this is
an inadequate vision of nature as well as an inaccurate view of human nature.
Ever since the Greeks and before (for instance, in much of the Old Testament),
"nature"--and in particular the notion of the "bestial"--has gotten a raw
deal. If, as Rousseau charges, we err by projecting back onto nature vices
that have only been cultivated by society so, too, I would argue, we flatter
ourselves by supposing that such virtues as a sense of justice are unique
to us and wholly foreign to nature.
HOBBES WAS WRONG--PEOPLE AREN'T
NATURALLY VIOLENT AND SELFISH
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.108.
On the other hand, it is too easy
to move from the natural violence of tooth and claw to the conclusion that
we too are by nature part of that Darwinian panorama, except for the conventions
of society and the rational control cultivated by society. But this seems
wrong on at least two counts: First of all, it presumes a view of human
nature that is as dubious as it is unflattering. I have already argued
at length that we are not--contra Hobbes--naturally violent and selfish
creatures who abstain from attacking one another only because of legal
restraint and awe for the power of the state.
HOBBES AND ROUSSEAU OVEREMPHASIZE
THE SURVIVAL MOTIVE
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.117.
But the question is based on the
obviously fraudulent presupposition that every individual strives first
and foremost for its own interests and survival. Hobbes marked this off
as the one natural right that no state or power could abridge, and even
Rousseau took individual self-preservation to be the preeminent natural
sentiment. Moral philosophers have long struggled against the presumption
that every human action--moral or not--is ultimately motivated by self-interest,
and evolutionists used to take it as a matter of course that the struggle
for individual survival and self-preservation is the first principle of
biology. But moral philosophers have come to the conclusion, in various
ways, that not all motivation is self-interested and that moral motivation,
in particular, is not and perhaps must not be self-interested. Evolutionary
biologists have similarly come to the conclusion that the struggle for
survival and self-preservation, even if primary, does not take place on
the level of the individual organism.
HOBBES CHARACTERISTICS DESCRIBED
AS NATURAL WERE LEARNED VICES
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.151-2.
Our so-called autonomy and individuality
are not natural endowments at all but, quite the contrary, characteristics
learned and cultivated in a particular kind of society, as are our rationality
and our ability to negotiate contracts and other agreements with other
people. Hobbesian greed and selfishness are not so much aspects of "human
nature" as they are learned and cultivated social vices. (Rousseau was
quite right when he diagnosed the Hobbesian "state of nature" as in fact
a pathological projection of a certain sort of society, ascribing to nature
the vices of Hobbes's own society.) If only Rousseau had followed through
with his own observation and not himself ascribed so much to "natural man"
that could only have been given him by society. It is true that we are
naturally benign, as Rousseau so happily argued, but we are so not because
we are indifferent to our fellow creatures but because we are already beholden
to them and responsive to their behavior. Our "natural goodness" is nothing
but reciprocal altruism in circumstances of plenty and in the absence of
the more vicious status-games of the world Rousseau rightly so despised.
HOBBES VIEW OF HUMAN NATURE ENCOURAGES
A PASSION FOR VENGEANCE
ROBERT SOLOMON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF TEXAS, A PASSION FOR JUSTICE, 1990, P.278.
How did our passion for retribution--our
need for vengeance--come about? I think that my evolutionary speculations
in Chapter 3 go a long way in answering this question. In that chapter,
I was primarily concerned to account for our "natural" sympathies and our
sense of fellowship with others, as opposed to the antagonistic, competitive
view of the "state of nature" described by writers like Hobbes.
THE FEAR OF DEATH ISN'T EVERYONE'S
DOMINANT MOTIVE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.57.
Hobbes's intellectual audacity
is remarkable, but in several respects problematic. He wished to demonstrate
that for every human being, obedience to the sovereign is a necessary deduction
from his (or her) very nature. For this he relies, crucially, on the postulate
that every human being's strongest passion is necessarily aversion to death.
But must it be? Was the Civil War due purely to men's failure to appreciate
their true interest? What of those who might have claimed that their strongest
passion was a desire for eternal bliss in a life after death, or to glorify
God? Hobbes's answer is that God commands the laws of nature, and thereby
obedience to the sovereign (HL, 217). But this really introduces into the
argument an extraneous element out of keeping with its general tenor.
HOBBES' ONE-SIDED VIEW OF HUMAN
NATURE UNDERMINES HIS POLITICS
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.13.
One of the basic problems of Hobbes's
political philosophy is precisely his one-sided characterization of human
nature as essentially antisocial. It is true that people sometimes struggle
for what they want or need by using violence. It is also true that some
people distrust others and that some are concerned with their reputations.
Yet, from this it does not follow that these are the essential characteristics
of human nature. What does follow is that various individuals act from
various motives and various reasons in their everyday life. We cannot encapsulate
human nature, as Hobbes tries to do' by reducing it to a certain number
of antisocial traits and leaving out other traits.
HOBBES NEGLECTS HUMANS' SOCIAL NATURE
DAVID GAUTHIER, PROFESSOR OF PHILSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF PITTSBURGH, MORALS BY AGREEMENT, 1986, P.319-20.
Hobbes offers the most unified
and compelling psychological portrayal of economic man. But the society
that with matchless consistency he generates from purely asocial motivations,
is primarily an instrument for cutting the costs of human interaction,
for eliminating the hostility found in the natural condition of humankind.
It is true that when Hobbes catalogues the ills of this natural condition,
he refers to the lack of arts, letters and society (that is social intercourse),
of commodious building, navigation, and mechanical contrivances, but the
emphasis is on the shortness and nastiness of life. Hobbes had little sense
of the positive benefits of interaction, and no sense at all, or so it
would seem, of the progressive benefits-of the prospect of, not merely
an improved lot, but a continually improving lot, for human beings in a
condition of society. The psychological grasp of asociality implicit in
Hobbes's argument is thus not matched by a comparable degree of social
or economic insight.
HOBBES' THEORY FAILS - IT'S BASED
ON EXTREME CASE CIVIL WAR
LEO STRAUSS, POLITICAL THEORIST,
UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO, NATURAL RIGHT AND HISTORY, 1953, P.196.
Hobbes's political doctrine is
meant to be universally applicable and hence to be applicable also and
especially in extreme cases. This indeed may be said to be the boast of
the classic doctrine of sovereignty: that it gives its due to the extreme
case, to what holds good in emergency situations, whereas those who question
that doctrine are accused of not looking beyond the pale of normality.
Accordingly, Hobbes built his whole moral and political doctrine on observations
regarding the extreme case; for the experience on which his doctrine of
the state of nature is based is the experience of civil war. It is in the
extreme situation, when the social fabric has completely broken down, that
there comes to sight the solid foundation on which every social order must
ultimately rest: the fear of violent death, which is the strongest force
in human life. Yet Hobbes was forced to concede that the fear of violent
death is only "commonly'' or in most cases the most powerful force. The
principle which was supposed to make possible a political doctrine of universal
applicability, then, is not universally valid and therefore is useless
in what, from Hobbes's point of view, is the most important case-the extreme
case. For how can one exclude the possibility that precisely in the extreme
situation the exception will prevail? |
JOHN LOCKE WAS RIGHT!
THE CONTRACT IS JUSTIFIED BY NATURAL
FREEDOM AND EQUALITY
JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF
GOVERNMENT, (HACKETT EDITION), 1690, P.52.
Men being, as has been said, by
nature, all free, equal, and independent, no one can be put out of this
estate, and subjected to the political power of another, without his own
consent. The only way whereby any one divests himself of his natural liberty,
and puts on the bonds of civil society, is by agreeing with other men to
join and unite into a community for their comfortable, safe, and peaceable
living one amongst another, in a secure enjoyment of their properties,
and a greater security against any, that are not of it. This any number
of men may do, because it injures not the freedom of the rest; they are
left as they were in the liberty of the state of nature. When any number
of men have so consented to make one community or government, they are
thereby presently incorporated, and make one body politic, wherein the
majority have a right to act and conclude the rest.
THE STATE OF NATURE IS A STATE OF
FREEDOM AND EQUALITY
JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF
GOVERNMENT, (HACKETT EDITION), 1690, P.8.
To understand political power right,
and derive it from its original, we must consider, what state all men are
naturally in, and that is, a state of perfect freedom to order their actions,
and dispose of their possessions and persons, as they think fit, within
the bounds of the law of nature, without asking leave, or depending upon
the will of any other man. A state also of equality, wherein all the power
and jurisdiction is reciprocal, no one having more than another; there
being nothing more evident, than that creatures of the same species and
rank, promiscuously born to all the same advantages of nature, and the
use of the same faculties, should also be equal one amongst another without
subordination or subjection, unless the lord and master of them all should,
by any manifest declaration of his will, set one above another, and confer
on him, by an evident and clear appointment, an undoubted right to dominion
and sovereignty.
THE STRONGEST RULE IN THE STATE
OF NATURE
JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF
GOVERNMENT, (HACKETT EDITION), 1690, P.66.
Thirdly, In the state of nature
there often wants power to back and support the sentence when right, and
to give it due execution. They who by any injustice offended, will seldom
fail, where they are able, by force to make good their injustice; such
resistance many times makes the punishment dangerous, and frequently destructive,
to those who attempt it.
REASON SUPPORTS THE SANCTITY OF
LIFE, LIBERTY, AND PROPERTY
JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF
GOVERNMENT, (HACKETT EDITION), 1690, P.9.
The state of nature has a law of
nature to govern it, which obliges every one: and reason, which is that
law, teaches all mankind, who will but consult it, that being all equal
and independent, no one ought to harm another in his life, health, liberty,
or possessions: for men being all the workmanship of one omnipotent, and
infinitely wise maker; all the servants of one sovereign master, sent into
the world by his order, and about his business; they are his property,
whose workmanship they are, made to last during his, not one another's
pleasure: and being furnished with like faculties, sharing all in one community
of nature, there cannot be supposed any such subordination among us, that
may authorize us to destroy one another, as if we were made for one another's
uses, as the inferior ranks of creatures are for our's.
PEOPLE MUST PRESERVE LIFE, LIBERTY,
AND PROPERTY OF OTHERS
JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF
GOVERNMENT, (HACKETT EDITION), 1690, P.9.
Every one, as he is bound to preserve
himself, and not to quit his station wilfully, so by the like reason, when
his own preservation comes not in competition, ought he, as much as he
can, to preserve the rest of mankind, and may not, unless it be to do justice
on an offender, take away, or impair the life, or what tends to the preservation
of the life, the liberty, health, limb, or goods of another.
LOCKE OPPOSES ARBITRARY GOVERNMENT
C.B. MACPHERSON, PROFESSOR OF POLITICAL
ECONOMY, UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO, INTRODUCTION TO LOCKE'S SECOND TREATISE
OF GOVERNMENT, 1980, P.XX.
His argument against arbitrary
government has attracted most attention, and it is indeed important. Men,
being so appetitive and contentious, have no choice but to hand over all
their natural rights and powers, including their jurisdiction over their
own properties, to a sovereign civil society ( 120), but it would contradict
the purpose for which they did so if they were to authorize an absolute
or arbitrary government ( 137). Hence Locke's insistence that the right
of taxation must rest with the majority of the people, or with the majority
of their elected representatives (which means, as we have seen, the majority
of those elected by the property owners). Apart from this right of taxation,
which only the majority of their representatives may exercise, no government
can ever have any right to take any part of any man's property without
his own consent ( 138). Even absolute power, which must sometimes be granted
(as to military commanders over their subordinates), is not arbitrary power:
it gives the power of life and death but not a power over a soldier's property
( 139).
GOVERNMENT POWER IS LIMITED
C.B. Macpherson, Professor of Political
Economy, University of Toronto, introduction to Locke's SECOND TREATISE
OF GOVERNMENT, 1980, p.xx.
Not only are the powers of any
government thus limited: the whole power of any constituted legislature,
and therefore of any other part of a government, is revocable: the legislative
power (which must be supreme within any frame of government) "being only
a fiduciary power to act for certain ends, there remains still in the people
a supreme power to remove or alter the legislative, when they find the
legislative act contrary to the trust reposed in them" ( 149, cf. 222).
The authority of any government is conditional on its performing the functions
for which it was entrusted with power.
ABSOLUTE MONARCHY IS INCONSISTENT
WITH CIVIL SOCIETY
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.62-3.
'Absolute monarchs are but men',
Locke reminds us, and great as are the inconveniences of the state of nature
due to men's being judges in their own case, yet they would have done better
to remain in that state than, when quitting it, to agree 'that all of them
but one should be under the restraint of laws, but that he should still
retain all the liberty of the state of nature, increased with power, and
made licentious by impunity. This is to think that men are so foolish that
they take care to avoid what mischiefs may be done them by polecats or
foxes, but are content, nay think it safely, to be devoured by lions.'
This is a deservedly famous piece of rhetoric. But Locke has a subtler
and no less effective argument: absolute monarchy is actually inconsistent
with civil society, for the absolute ruler remains judge in his own case
- between him and his subjects there is no common, impartial judge, and
a common impartial judge is precisely the institution that distinguishes
civil society from the state of nature (L, 9,47,45).
EVEN IN THE STATE OF NATURE, FAIR
PUNISHMENT IS PROPORTIONATE
JOHN LOCKE, SECOND TREATISE OF
GOVERNMENT, (HACKETT EDITION), 1690, P.10.
And thus, in the state of nature,
one man comes by a power over another; but yet no absolute or arbitrary
power, to use a criminal, when he has got him in his hands, according to
the passionate heats, or boundless extravagancy of his own will; but only
to retribute to him, so far as calm reason and conscience dictate, what
is proportionate to his transgression, which is so much as may serve for
reparation and restraint: for these two are the only reasons, why one man
may lawfully do harm to another, which is that we call punishment.
THE LOCKEAN APPROACH TO GOVERNMENT
HAS MOST BENEFITED HUMANITY
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.647.
Enlightened self-interest is, of
course, not the loftiest of motives, but those who decry it often substitute,
by accident or design, motives which are much worse, such as hatred, envy,
and love of power. On the whole, the school which owed its origin to Locke,
and which preached enlightened self-interest, did more to increase human
happiness, and less to increase human misery, than was done by the schools
which despised it in the name of heroism and self-sacrifice. I do not forget
the horrors of early industrialism, but these, after all, were mitigated
within the system. And I set against them Russian serfdom, the evils of
war and its aftermath of fear and hatred, and the inevitable obscurantism
of those who attempt to preserve ancient systems when they have lost their
vitality. |
JOHN LOCKE WAS WRONG!
LOCKE'S DEPICTION OF THE STATE OF
NATURE IS CONTRADICTORY
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.60.
Locke thus denies that the state
of nature is a state of war. What defines the state of nature, he says,
is that men live together without a 'common judge with authority' over
them; but this state is (or at least should be) a state of 'peace, good
will, mutual assistance and preservation'. Yet Locke admits that, given
the lack of a common judge, 'the state of war once begun continues' and
that escaping from 'this state of war...is one great reason of men's putting
themselves into society and quitting the state of nature' (L, 11-12). Locke
has here attempted an impossible amalgam of the Hobbesian account with
a contrary stoic-derived 'golden age' conception of the state of nature
- the latter being quite unsuited to a contract theory of government. In
the end, therefore, he has not succeeded in disagreeing with Hobbes on
this point.
LOCKE FAILS TO EFFECTIVELY JUSTIFY
A NATURAL LAW
JAN NARVESON, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
UNIVERSITY OF WATERLOO, THE LIBERTARIAN IDEA, 1988, P.148-9.
Many philosophers, such as Aquinas
and John Locke, have held that there is a "natural law". This idea was
not clarified by these philosophers, although that they had fairly explicit
ideas about its content. Aquinas, for example, held that natural law (like
all law) had to be for the "common good". And Locke in particular held
that the natural law forbids all to refrain from injuring others in their
"life, health, liberty, and possessions". Their lack of articulation of
the concept of natural law, however, has left them short of adherents among
contemporary philosophers trained in the analytic tradition. Insofar as
they simply appeal to natural law without further explication or defense,
they are liable to all of the charges I have laid to the door of intuitionism
in all its forms.
LOCKE'S VIEW OF HUMAN NATURE WAS
FUNDAMENTALLY AMBIGUOUS
C.B. MACPHERSON, PROFESSOR OF POLITICAL
ECONOMY, UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO, INTRODUCTION TO LOCKE'S SECOND TREATISE
OF GOVERNMENT, 1980, P.XIV.
This ambiguity about the state
of nature simply reflects Locke's fundamental ambiguity about human nature.
In the first picture men generally are naturally reasonable enough to impose
on themselves individually the moral rules needed to curb their contentious
appetites. In the second picture they are not: the greater part are "no
strict observers of equity and justice" ( 123), and none can secure themselves
individually. Locke needed both these inconsistent assumptions about human
nature in order to make his case, which was that individuals must be understood
to have agreed to give up their natural rights and powers to an all-powerful
civil society, but that the civil society (themselves when so united) could
not conceivably have delegated absolute or arbitrary power to any government,
but must be understood to have retained the right to alter the frame of
government whenever they (acting by a majority of themselves) so desired.
LOCKE ENTRENCHED CLASS DISTINCTIONS
TO UPHOLD PRIVATE PROPERTY
C.B. MACPHERSON, PROFESSOR OF POLITICAL
ECONOMY, UNIVERSITY OF TORONTO, INTRODUCTION TO LOCKE'S SECOND TREATISE
OF GOVERNMENT, 1980, P.XVIII-XIX.
This creates a further problem.
If there was the class-division be ore the institution of civil society
and government, and if the purpose of instituting them was the protection
of this unequal property, why would those without property agree to enter
civil society and thus give up their natural right of protecting themselves)
They would have good reason to do so if they were to become full members
of civil society, for then they would be the majority. But if they were
full members they might use their majority power to legislate a levelling
of property. Locke did not see this as a problem for he never intended
them to be full members. He took for granted that the right to vote in
elections to the legislature was to be confined to the propertied class.
Representation of cities and counties should be in proportion to the amount
they contributed in taxes (they were to be fully bound by the laws: everyone
is obliged, whether "his possession be of land, to him and his heirs for
ever, or a lodging only for a week; or whether it be barely travelling
freely on the highway" ( 119). Both the exclusion of those without estate
from the law-making process, and their subjection to the law, were required
by the very purpose of civil government, the protection of life, liberty
and estate.
LOCKE FAILS TO JUSTIFY MAJORITY
RULE
Bertrand Russell, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, p.632-3.
The question of taxation might
be supposed to raise difficulties for Locke, but he perceives none. The
expense of government, he says, must be borne by the citizens, but with
their consent, i.e., with that of the majority. But why, one asks, should
the consent of the majority suffice? Every man's consent, we were told,
is necessary to justify the government in taking any part of his property.
I suppose his tacit consent to taxation in accordance with majority decision
is presumed to be involved in his citizenship, which, in turn, is presumed
to be voluntary. All this is, of course, sometimes quite contrary to the
facts. Most men have no effective liberty of choice as to the State to
which they shall belong, and very few have liberty, nowadays, to belong
to no State. Suppose, for example, you are a pacifist, and disapprove of
war. Wherever you live, the government will take some of your property
for warlike purposes. With what justice can you be compelled to submit
to this? I can imagine many answers, but I do not think any of them are
consistent with Locke's principles. He thrusts in the maxim of majority
rule without adequate consideration, and offers no transition to it from
his individualistic premisses, except the mythical social contract.
LOCKE'S HISTORICAL EXAMPLES DON'T
EXPLAIN THE ORIGIN GOVERNMENT
JEREMY WALDRON, PROFESSOR OF LAW,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO
RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.58.
Much the same is true of the instances
that Locke cites of contractualist foundation. For the deliberate institution
of government by free and equal individuals, we are given the classical
stories of the origins of Rome and Venice, and the founding of the Italian
city of Terentum by a group of Spartan exiles under Palantus in the eighth
century BC. And we are told that 'no Examples are so frequent in History.
. . as those of Men withdrawing themselves . . . from the Jurisdiction
they were born under, and the Family or Community they were bred up in,
and setting up new Governments in other places'. But these cases are just
not particularly telling, since they involve, not the foundation of a state
by people who till then had had no experience of the political, but the
foundation of a new state by exiles from an old one. As an account of the
original development of the political, they tell us nothing at all.
LOCKE'S HISTORICAL SUPPORT FOR THE
CONTRACT ISN'T COMPELLING
JEREMY WALDRON, PROFESSOR OF LAW,
UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA, BERKELEY, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO
RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.57-8.
We have seen already how sensitive
Locke was to the historical implausibility of the contract account, to
the 'mighty objection' often raised that history reveals no instances of
'a Company of Men, independent and equal one amongst another, that met
together, and in this way began and set up a government'. He responds to
the difficulty in a number of ways. Sometimes he writes as though the challenge
was purely and simply to produce 'instances' of people in the state of
nature, or 'instances' of the explicit contractual founding of a political
society. Thus, he writes sometimes as though the production of a single
counter-example would suffice to refute the objection, as though he were
trying to establish nothing more than the bare logical possibility of the
contractarian hypothesis. 'To those that say there were never any men in
the State of Nature', he responds by adducing Garcilaso de la Vega's account
of the two men of different nationalities who found it necessary to bargain
together for subsistence goods after they had been shipwrecked fortuitously
on the same desert island. But of course no example could be less apt if
Locke's intention here is to offer a historical instance of what things
were like in the first great era of human history or pre-history. Pedro
Serrano and the other shipwreck victim are not merely stuck in the most
bizarre and exceptional circumstances, but they are themselves castaways
from civilization and their ability to contract with one another, as much
as their ability to survive in these peculiar circumstances, arguably derives
from their previous socialization. If anything, the Garcilaso case favours
something like a Filmerian anthropology - as a classic example of the exception
that proves the rule.
LOCKE DEFINITELY BELIEVED IN A HISTORICAL
CONTRACT
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.60.
In Locke's case there is no room
for doubt that he believed the state of nature to be a historical phase
however brief - prior to government (L, 9,51-2 and passim). That apart,
his account of the contrast gives every appearance of aiming to correct
Hobbes's version.
LOCKE ASSUMES AN ACTUAL, HISTORICAL
CONTRACT
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.29.
Locke, unlike Hobbes, Rousseau,
and Kant, uses the concept of the state of nature in a historical sense.
He thinks of it as a historical fact set at some point in the distant past.
Like Hobbes, he argues that the concept of the state of nature amounts
to the absence of any political society; however, he does not think that
the absence of a political society precludes all other forms of social
relations.
RESIDENCE DOESN'T CREATE A DUTY
OF POLITICAL OBLIGATION
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.38.
According to Locke, a legitimate
government is any government that respects natural rights. If this is the
case, then there is a general obligation to obey such a government as long
as we openly or tacitly consent to it, provided it does not violate natural
rights. It does not seem to follow, however, that because we live in a
particular community we consent to all the rules and norms of this community.
What follows is that we should, as a matter of prudential consideration
(self-interest), consent to at least some of its rules and norms. Otherwise,
we would not be able to live in such a community because we would be permanently
ostracized by the rest of its members, or we would be physically eliminated
either by being jailed or executed. If we do not follow certain rules of
survival, such as not killing innocent people or not stealing from them,
we would not last long as members of a community. But, I would argue against
Locke, even if we were to live under a legitimate government (one that
respects important natural or moral rights) we would not have a general
obligation to obey it. The reason is that even a legitimate government
is not infallible and can sometimes make unjust rules. Thus, the fact that
we live under its jurisdiction is not morally sufficient to obligate us
to consent to all of its rules. We, as moral agents, have a greater obligation
not to consent to unjust rules.
FOR LOCKE, THE ONLY WAY TO REFUSE
CONSENT IS VOLUNTARY EXILE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.66-7.
These confusions aside, Locke's
extension of the concept of consent to include 'the very being of any one
within the territories' of a government has attracted much criticism. If
consent is understood as broadly as this, is there any way in which a person
could withhold his consent? Is Locke really allowing individuals any freedom
of choice in the matter, after all? The answer is that, for Locke, there
is only one way to refuse consent to an established government's authority
and that is, to keep out of its territory, or if in it, to leave it.
LOCKE LACKS AN EFFECTIVE MEANS FOR
RESOLVING DISPUTES OF PEOPLE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.84.
For his part, Locke argued that
the judge of whether a ruler had breached his trust should be 'the people',
but without specifying any possible way in which it could exercise this
role. So Locke's solution to the problem of adjudication is scarcely satisfactory,
while those of the papalists and Calvinists seem too much like special
pleading.
LOCKE FAILS TO ESTABLISH FAIR PROCESS
FOR DETERMINING GENERAL GOOD
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.631-2.
The power of the government by
contract, we are told, never extends beyond the common good. A moment ago
I quoted a sentence as to the powers of government, ending "and all this
only for the public good." It seems not to have occurred to Locke to ask
who was to be the judge of the common good. Obviously if the government
is the judge it will always decide in its own favour. Presumably Locke
would say that the majority of the citizens is to be the judge, But many
questions have to be decided too quickly for it to be possible to ascertain
the opinion of the electorate; of these peace and war are perhaps the most
important. The only remedy in such cases is to allow to public opinion
or its representatives some power--such as impeachment--of subsequently
punishing executive officers for acts that are found to have been unpopular.
But often this is a very inadequate remedy.
LOCKE'S PHILOSOPHY IS ANTIQUATED
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.640.
Locke's political philosophy was,
on the whole, adequate and useful until the industrial revolution. Since
then, it has been increasingly unable to tackle the important problems.
The power of property, as embodied in vast corporations, grew beyond anything
imagined by Locke. The necessary functions of the State--for example, in
education--increased enormously. Nationalism brought about an alliance,
sometimes an amalgamation, of economic and political power, making war
the principal means of competition. The single separate citizen has no
longer the power and independence that he had in Locke's speculations.
Our age is one of organization, and its conflicts are between organizations,
not between separate individuals. The state of nature, as Locke says, still
exists as between States. A new international Social Contract is necessary
before we can enjoy the promised benefits of government. When once an international
government has been created, much of Locke's political philosophy will
again become applicable, though not the part of it that deals with private
property.
THE CONDITIONS FOR LOCKEAN LIBERALISM
NO LONGER EXIST
WILLIAM OPHULS, FORMER PROFESSOR
OF POLITICAL SCIENCE, NORTHWESTERN AND A. STEPHEN BOYAN, PROFESSOR OF POLITICAL
SCIENCE, UNIVERSITY OF MARYLAND, ECOLOGY AND THE POLITICS OF SCARCITY REVISITED,
1992, P.204.
Thanks to the Great Frontier, Locke
and Smith found that there was so much abundance in the state of nature
that a Hobbesian war of all against all was unlikely; every person could
take away some kind of prize, and competition would be socially constructive
rather than destructive, with the "invisible hand" producing the greatest
good for the society as a whole. Thus government was required only to keep
the game honest-a mere referee, needing only modest powers and minimal
institutional machinery-and individuals could be left alone to pursue happiness
as they defined it without hindrance by society or the state. The frontier
is gone now, and we have encountered the limits of the commons. However,
the physical disappearance of the frontier was for a long time mitigated
by technology, which allowed us to graze more cows on the same amount of
pasture. Now we have reached the limits of technology: The cows are standing
almost shoulder to shoulder, many are starving, and the manure is piling
up faster than the commons can absorb it. All that remains is to alter
the rational, self-seeking behavior of the individuals and groups that
use the commons. This must be done by collective means, for the dynamic
of the tragedy of the commons is so powerful that individuals are virtually
powerless to extricate themselves unaided from its remorseless working.
Our political institutions must indeed force us to be free. |
JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU IS RIGHT!
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT ENHANCES INDIVIDUAL
SECURITY
JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL
CONTRACT (PENGUIN EDITION), 1762, P.77-8.
Granted these distinctions, it
becomes manifestly false to assert that individuals make any real renunciation
by the social contract; indeed, as a result of the contract they find themselves
in a situation preferable in real terms to that which prevailed before;
instead of an alienation, they have profitably exchanged an uncertain and
precarious life for a better and more secure one; they have exchanged natural
independence for freedom, the power to destroy others for the enjoyment
of their own security; they have exchanged their own strength which others
might overcome for a right which the social union makes invincible. Their
very lives, which they have pledged to the state, are always protected
by it; and even when they risk their lives to defend the state, what more
are they doing but giving back what they have received from the state?
What are they doing that they would not do more often, and at greater peril,
in the state of nature, where every man is inevitably at war and at the
risk of his life, defends whatever serves him to maintain life? Assuredly,
all must now fight in case of need for their country, but at least no one
has any longer to fight for himself. And is there not something to be gained
by running, for the sake of the guarantee of safety, a few of those risks
we should each have to face alone if we were deprived of that assurance?
FREEDOM IS THE ESSENCE OF HUMANITY
JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL
CONTRACT (PENGUIN EDITION), 1762, P.55.
To renounce freedom is to renounce
one's humanity, one's rights as a man and equally one's duties. There is
no possible quid, pro quo for one who renounces everything; indeed such
renunciation is contrary to man's very nature; for if you take away all
freedom of the will, you strip a man's actions of all moral significance.
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT ABOLISHES INDIVIDUAL
RIGHTS
JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL
CONTRACT (PENGUIN EDITION), 1762, P.60-1.
These articles of association,
rightly understood, are reducible to a single one, namely the total alienation
by each associate of himself and all his rights to the whole community.
Thus, in the first place, as every individual gives himself absolutely,
the conditions are the same for all, and precisely because they are the
same for all, it is in no one's interest to make the conditions onerous
for others. Secondly, since the alienation is unconditional, the union
is as perfect as it could be, and no individual associate has any longer
any rights to claim; for if rights were left to individuals, in the absence
of any higher authority to judge between them and the public, each individual,
being his own judge in some causes, would soon demand to be his own judge
in all; and in this way the state of nature would be kept in being, and
the association inevitably become either tyrannical or void.
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT INVOLVES SUBMISSION
TO THE GENERAL WILL
JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU, THE SOCIAL
CONTRACT (PENGUIN EDITION), 1762, P.61.
Finally, since each man gives himself
to all, he gives himself to no one; and since there is no associate over
whom he does not gain the same rights as others gain over him, each man
recovers the equivalent of everything he loses, and in the bargain he acquires
more power to preserve what he has. If, then, we eliminate from the social
pact everything that is not essential to it, we find it comes down to this:
'Each one of us puts into the community his person and all his powers under
the supreme direction of the general will; and as a body, we incorporate
every member as an indivisible part of the whole.'
UNLIKE HOBBES, ROUSSEAU SOUGHT TO
PRESERVE LIBERTY
JEREMY JENNINGS, PROFESSOR OF POLITICS,
UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER
AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.117.
The implications of these ideas
upon Rousseau's conception of contract were necessarily profound, and this
because the 'fundamental problem' he thus set himself was nothing less
than that of squaring the circle: how to find a form of association which
will defend the person and goods of each member with the collective force
of all and under which each individual, while uniting himself with the
others, obeys no one but himself and remains as free as before. The contrast
with the position endorsed by Hobbes could not have been more stark. As
Hobbes perceived it, the human condition was so bleak that men could escape
from the war of all against all only by agreeing to transfer lock, stock
and barrel their natural right to govern and to arbitrate in disputes to
the single sovereign power of Leviathan, preserving only their right to
self-preservation. The trade-off was a straightforward one: life and an
element of liberty in exchange for obedience to the sword. For Rousseau
there was to be no trade-off, there were to be no losses, only gains. Men,
he believed, could have both liberty and law if they were able to construct
a society where they ruled themselves.
ROUSSEAU UPHOLDS THE BASIC RIGHTS
TO LIFE AND LIBERTY
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.57.
He defends the natural rights to
life and liberty, although, unlike Locke, he considers the right to property
to be a conventional rather than a natural right. Moreover, in The Social
Contract he argues against the institution of slavery and defends the natural
right to liberty on these grounds: To renounce one's liberty is to renounce
one's quality as a man. the rights and also the duties of humanity....
Such a renunciation is incompatible with man's nature, for to take away
all freedom from his will is to take away all morality from his action.
Rousseau's contract is intended to guarantee both the enjoyment of civil
and political freedom and the right to private property. It guarantees,
among other things, the right to have an equal voice in the making of laws
and hence the right to vote. Moreover, the right to political freedom derives
from the natural right to liberty.
SOVEREIGNTY REMAINS WITH THE PEOPLE,
TYRANNY IS IMPOSSIBLE
VICENTE MEDINA, PROFESSOR OF PHILOSOPHY,
BERGEN COMMUNITY COLLEGE, SOCIAL CONTRACT THEORIES: POLITICAL OBLIGATION
OR ANARCHY?, 1990, P.59.
Thus Rousseau unlike Locke, does
not postulate a right to revolution against tyranny. He does not need this
right because sovereignty remains always with the people. In Rousseau's
Republic, tyranny or any sort of gross injustice on the part of the sovereign
would be impossible. The general will of the people can never be unjust,
"since no one is unjust to himself." The sovereign therefore is always
what "it ought lo be."
ROUSSEAU EFFECTIVELY PRESERVES EQUALITY
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.81-2.
A noteworthy feature of Rousseau's
theory is that it shows him to be unique among the many social contract
theorists who have postulated man's liberty and equality in a state of
nature in that he wishes to preserve both their liberty and their equality
in the civil state. His ideal constitution does indeed preserve this equality,
thus making Rousseau the great exponent of what may be called the 'democratic'
social contract (though he himself uses the term 'democracy' in a different
sense.
ROUSSEAU'S MADE SOVEREIGNTY A PERMANENT
POSSESSION
JEREMY JENNINGS, PROFESSOR OF POLITICS,
UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER
AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.117.
What marked Rousseau out from his
predecessors was that they, unlike him, saw active sovereignty as being
only the people's temporary possession, as something that was to be handed
over to the appropriate authority as soon as possible, only rarely (and
in some cases never) to be reclaimed. Pufendorf, for example, even went
so far as to define the handing over of the right to govern by a defeated
people as a meaningful form of consent. Not only was Rousseau unwilling
to grant that sovereignty could be given away either under duress or by
tacit agreement but also he even opposed its voluntary and unforced transfer.
Sovereignty, in short, was not like a piece of property that could be freely
disposed of: it was an inalienable possession, part of the individual's
very humanity. Rousseau's contribution, as Robert Derathe has argued, was
therefore to attribute not only the origin but also the exercise of sovereignty
to the people. |
JEAN-JACQUES ROUSSEAU IS WRONG!
ROUSSEAU'S THEORIES TEND TO JUSTIFY
THE TOTALITARIAN STATE
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.694.
Rousseau's political theory is
set forth in his Social Contract, published in 1762. This book is very
different in character from most of his writing; it contains little sentimentality
and much close intellectual reasoning. Its doctrines, though they pay lip-service
to democracy, tend to the justification of the totalitarian State.
ROUSSEAU PRIORITIZED EQUALITY AT
THE EXPENSE OF LIBERTY
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.695.
Although the book as a whole is
much less rhetorical than most of Rousseau's writing, the first chapter
opens with a very forceful piece of rhetoric: "Man is born free, and everywhere
he is in chains. One man thinks himself the master of others, but remains
more of a slave than they are." Liberty is the nominal goal of Rousseau's
thought, but in fact it is equality that he values, and that he seeks to
secure even at the expense of liberty.
ROUSSEAU'S CONTRACT IS ESSENTIALLY
HOBBESIAN
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.695.
His conception of the Social Contract
seems, at first, analogous to Locke's, but soon shows itself more akin
to that of Hobbes. In the development from the state of nature, there comes
a time when individuals can no longer maintain themselves in primitive
independence; it then becomes necessary to self-preservation that they
should unite to form a society. But how can I pledge my liberty without
harming my interests? "The problem is to find a form of association which
will defend and protect with the whole common force the person and goods
of each associate, and in which each, while uniting himself with all, may
still obey himself alone, and remain as free as before. This is the fundamental
problem of which the Social Contract provides the solution."
ROUSSEAU CALLS FOR THE COMPLETE
ABROGATION OF LIBERTY
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.695-6.
The Contract consists in "the total
alienation of each associate, together with all his rights, to the whole
community; for, in the first place, as each gives himself absolutely, the
conditions are the same for all; and this being so, no one has any interest
in making them burdensome to others." The alienation is to be without reserve:
"If individuals retained certain rights, as there would be no common superior
to decide between them and the public, each, being on one point his own
judge, would ask to be so on all; the state of nature would thus continue,
and the association would necessarily become inoperative or tyrannical."
This implies a complete abrogation of liberty and a complete rejection
of the doctrine of the rights of man. It is true that, in a later chapter,
there is some softening of this theory. It is there said that, although
the social contract gives the body politic absolute power over all its
members, nevertheless human beings have natural rights as men. The sovereign
cannot impose upon its subjects any fetters that are useless to the community,
nor can it even wish to do so." But the sovereign is the sole judge of
what is useful or useless to the community. It is clear that only a very
feeble obstacle is thus opposed to collective tyranny. It should be observed
that the "sovereign" means, in Rousseau, not the monarch or the government,
but the community in its collective and legislative capacity.
ROUSSEAU'S CONCEPT OF FREEDOM IS
ORWELLIAN
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.697.
This conception of being "forced
to be free" is very metaphysical. The general will in the time of Galileo
was certainly anti-Copernican; was Galileo "forced to be free" when the
Inquisition compelled him to recant? Is even a malefactor "forced to be
free" when he is put in prison? Think of Byron's Corsair: "O'er the glad
waters of the deep blue sea, Our thoughts as boundless and our hearts as
free." Would this man be more "free" in a dungeon? The odd thing is that
Byron's noble pirates are a direct outcome of Rousseau, and yet, in the
above passage, Rousseau forgets his romanticism and speaks like a sophistical
policeman. Hegel, who owed much to Rousseau, adopted his misuse of the
word "freedom," and defined it as the right to obey the police, or something
not very different.
ROUSSEAU SUPPORTS RELIGIOUS OPPRESSION
MAURICE CRANSTON, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICAL SCIENCE, LONDON SCHOOL OF ECONOMICS, INTRODUCTION TO ROUSSEAU'S
THE SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1968, P.40.
In the Social Contract, however,
his attitude is very much closer to that of Machiavelli than it is to that
of Locke. What the state needs, Rousseau says in his chapter on the civil
religion, is a religion subordinate to the state and designed to teach
patriotic, civic and martial virtues. And Christianity, he says, quite
as boldly as Machiavelli, is no good for this purpose; it teaches men to
love the kingdom of heaven instead of their own republic on earth, and
it teaches them to suffer but not to fight. It teaches the wrong virtues.
Assuredly, Rousseau makes clear that he is talking here about civil religion,
not private religion, and he admits that 'the religion of the Gospel' is
the word of God for the private person. But the state religion is the more
important, and the state religion must be supreme; Rousseau even goes so
far as to propose a death penalty for those whose conduct is at variance
with the religious principles they proclaim.
ROUSSEAU WOULD PROHIBIT PRIVATE
ASSOC TO UPHOLD THE GENERAL WILL
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.699.
In Rousseau's opinion, what interferes
in practice with the expression of the general will is the existence of
subordinate associations within the State. Each of these will have its
own general will, which may conflict with that of the community as a whole.
"It may then be said that there are no longer as many votes as there are
men, but only as many as there are associations." This leads to an important
consequence: "It is therefore essential, if the general will is to be able
to express itself, that there should be no partial society within the State,
and that each citizen should think only his own thoughts: which was indeed
the sublime and unique system established by the great Lycurgus." In a
footnote, Rousseau supports his opinion with the authority of Machiavelli.
Consider what such a system would involve in practice. The State would
have to prohibit churches (except a State Church), political parties, trade-unions,
and all other organizations of men with similar economic interests. The
result is obviously the Corporate or Totalitarian State, in which the individual
citizen is powerless.
ROUSSEAU'S INFLUENCE LED TO DICTATORSHIP
BERTRAND RUSSELL, A HISTORY OF
WESTERN PHILOSOPHY, 1945, P.700-1.
The Social Contract became the
Bible of most of the leaders in the French Revolution, but no doubt, as
is the fate of Bibles, it was not carefully read and was still less understood
by many of its disciples. It reintroduced the habit of metaphysical abstractions
among the theorists of democracy, and by its doctrine of the general will
it made possible the mystic identification of a leader with his people,
which has no need of confirmation by so mundane an apparatus as the ballot-box.
Much of its philosophy could be appropriated by Hegel in his defence of
the Prussian autocracy. Its first-fruits in practice was the reign of Robespierre;
the dictatorships of Russia and Germany (especially the latter) are in
part an outcome of Rousseau's teaching. What further triumphs the future
has to offer to his ghost I do not venture to predict.
ROUSSEAU SUCCESSORS SAW HIS WORK
AS ABSOLUTIST
JEREMY JENNINGS, PROFESSOR OF POLITICS,
UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER
AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.129.
A contemporary writer as perceptive
and gifted as Carole Pateman has drawn attention to Rousseau as a critic
of what she describes as 'the fraudulent liberal social contract'. The
liberal contract, she argues, serves to justify social relationships and
political institutions that already exist whilst Rousseau's contract provides
'an actual foundation for a participatory political order of the future'.
The latter's democratic social contract, she goes on, is one of association
based on self-assumed obligation and of substantive equality between 'active
citizens who are political decision-makers'. From our brief survey of political
thought in the first half of the nineteenth century it is clear that there
were few in France who saw it that way. The republicans, with their passion
for the one and indivisible Republic, would perhaps have been able to make
sense of this description but for the rest the experience of the French
Revolution had been such as to convince them that Rousseau and his idea
of social contract had merely transposed the absolutism of government on
to another plane. Sovereignty was presumed to reside in the people, the
state had been left intact, and thus the modern Leviathan had been created.
This, Rousseau's critics concurred, had been a catastrophe without precedent.
For them it was quite definitely a case of la faute a Rousseau.
ROUSSEAU'S CONTRACT LEAD TO STATISM
JEREMY JENNINGS, PROFESSOR OF POLITICS,
UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER
AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.128
The force of Proudhon's argument
was that Rousseau had provided a spurious, if brilliantly oratorical, defence
of the domination of the state, in this case the one and indivisible Jacobin
Republic. Yet Proudhon, unlike other of Rousseau's critics, did not want
to abandon the idea of contract. Far from it: it was precisely the idea
of what Proudhon termed the 'free contract' that would lead to the dissolution
and ultimate disappearance of the state. The key here was what Proudhon
saw as the transition from distributive justice, defined as the reign of
law and as feudal, governmental and military rule, to commutative justice,
the dominance of the economic and industrial system. It was by moving away
from politics to economics that his preferred model of decentralized and
pluralistic self-government mutualism - would come into existence.
ROUSSEAU'S WORK INSPIRED THE FRENCH
REVOLUTIONARY DICTATORSHIP
JEREMY JENNINGS, PROFESSOR OF POLITICS,
UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER
AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.120.
But stated in this way we have
no sense of the emotional (and frequently tearful) frenzy that Rousseau
induced amongst his disciples. The community born out of the social contract
was to be frugal, hard working, virtuous, distrustful of wealth, free of
corruption, trusting to the simple qualities of the people cast as the
repositories of all that was good in society. Armed thus men such as Robespierre
and Saint-Just had little difficulty affirming their own rhetorical and
moral ascendancy over opponents that bore the mark of absolute evil. What
happened when the people were found to be unworthy of the love that had
been invested in them was the recourse to an ever-extensive dictatorship,
the combination of virtue and terror, with the general will of society
supposedly articulated by a twelve-man Committee of Public Safety.
ROUSSEAU PROVIDED THEORETICAL SUPPORT
FOR DESPOTISM
JEREMY JENNINGS, PROFESSOR OF POLITICS,
UNIVERSITY OF WALES, THE SOCIAL CONTRACT FROM HOBBES TO RAWLS, DAVID BOUCHER
AND PAUL KELLY, EDS., 1994, P.126.
Constant, like Mill after him,
was eager to establish that there was a part of human existence which 'by
necessity remains individual and independent' end which therefore was properly
beyond social control. Rousseau, he remarked, 'overlooked this truth',
thus providing theoretical support for despotism. And here was the heart
of the problem. Rousseau, Constant argued, defined the contract struck
between society and its members as the complete alienation of each individual
with all his rights, without any reservations, to the community. In order
to reassure us about the consequences of such an absolute renunciation
of all parts of our existence for the benefit of an abstract being, he
tells us that the sovereign, that is the social body, can neither harm
the totality of its members, nor any of them in particular. Since everyone
gives himself entirely, all share the same condition, and nobody is interested
in making the condition onerous to others. Because every individual gives
himself entirely to all, he does not give himself to anyone in particular.
Everybody acquires over his associates the same rights as he surrenders
in their favour. Thus he gains the equivalent of all that he loses together
with the greater strength to preserve what he has.
ROUSSEAU DENIES NECESSARY RIGHTS
OF RESISTANCE TO THE STATE
MICHAEL LESSNOFF, PROFESSOR OF
POLITICS, UNIVERSITY OF GLASGOW, SOCIAL CONTRACT, 1986, P.80.
Rousseau makes it clear that this
sovereign political authority consisting of all citizens is both supreme
and unlimited. It is an absolute sovereignty. The individual associates
who are parties to the contract cannot retain any of their rights; if they
did Rousseau suggests 'there would be no common superior to decide between
them and the public each being . . . his own judge' and the state of nature
would in effect continue (R 174 176). It looks as if Rousseau is here trying
to avoid the kind of resistance to authority and consequent civil turbulence
that is legitimated by Locke's theory of natural rights. This is understandable
in view of the fact that the constitution prescribed by Rousseau in The
Social Contract is that of an ideal state where it might be hoped such
resistance would have no place. But it remains questionable whether any
constitution can be so ideal as to ensure this. |