"Nominalism's Modal Paradise Lost," Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy (forthcoming).
Nominalism in all of its manifestations, from Abelard to Quine, grows out of ontological scruples. For William Ockham and his followers in the fourteenth century, nominalism was centrally concerned with a more parsimonious treatment of the ten Aristotelian categories of being. But when it came to the alethic modalities of possibility and necessity, the nominalist program suddenly turns expansive, or so it has seemed to recent commentators, who have found in the nominalists a commitment to vast realms of merely possible beings, and even to a possible-worlds semantics for modality. Here I argue that, quite contrary to how the nominalists are generally read, they take particular care to avoid an ontological commitment to possibilia. Indeed, although their broader semantic views make it quite natural for them to analyze modal sentences in terms of possible worlds, they deliberately eschew this way of proceeding, even at the cost of foregoing the explanatory power that their semantic theories have in other domains.
"Who Killed the Causality of Things?" Nous (forthcoming).
It's a familiar claim in recent philosophy that causation is a relationship between events. But, famously, things didn't used to be that way. Throughout antiquity, the Middle Ages and the early modern period, causation was understood as a relationship between substances and/or powers. When did this sort of "thing causation" die? And who killed it? The answer turns out to be surprising.
I am deep into writing a book on voluntarism in the later Middle Ages. The goal is to look very widely at the many aspects of voluntarism, as it concerns not just the scholastic debate over free will but also in ethics, politics, and literature.
Does philosophy make progress? If so, why bother studying its history? The answer I offer here is that we should study it because it is beautiful. Written for the 2011 PhilProgress symposium at Harvard.