Philosophy 5340
Topic : Introduction: Epistemology
and Philosophy

1. Introductory
Discussion: Epistemology and Philosophy
1.1 What is Philosophy?
Pap and Edwards defined "philosophy" as follows:
"Philosophy is concerned with the
justification of basic human beliefs and with the analysis of the
concepts in terms of which those beliefs are expressed."
According to this definition, philosophy involves two central tasks:
(1) Analysis of Fundamental Concepts;
(2) Inquiry into the Justification of
Basic Beliefs.
Many philosophers would, however, also add either or both of the
following tasks:
(3) The Discovery of Necessary Truths
This activity is closely related
to that of analysis, as it concerns the relationships between
fundamental concepts: philosophers attempt to establish truths
involving those concepts that could not be otherwise, that are
necessary. Some examples:
1. In science fiction stories – such as The Terminator – people
sometimes travel backwards into the past. Many philosophers have
been interested in how the concept of causation is related to the idea
of being earlier than, and some have claimed that it is logically
impossible for a cause to be later than its effect. If this is
right, then time travel is impossible, since time travel involves
causes that occur later than their effects. (The person who
travels back into the past remembers events that happen later on, in
the future, so those later events are causes of the memories he has at
the earlier time in the past.)
2. How is the concept of the mind related to the concept of
physical objects and events? Is it logically possible – as many
philosophers and scientists today claim – that the mind is just the
brain, and that consciousness is just a neural process? Or is it
logically impossible, as other philosophers have claimed, for the
mental to be identical with anything physical?
The discovery of necessary truths
also plays a crucial role with regard to the second task of philosophy
mentioned above – that is, inquiry into the justification of basic
beliefs. Here are two illustrations:
1. In thinking about the justification of beliefs, it is natural
to think of some beliefs as justified on the basis of other beliefs
that serve as evidence. The question then arises whether there
are some beliefs that can be justified even if there are no other
beliefs that provide evidential support for them. Let us
introduce, then, the distinction between inferentially justified
beliefs and non-inferentially justified beliefs. Given that
distinction, one can then ask whether, for example, the following
proposition is a necessary truth:
(a) No belief can be justified unless some belief is non-inferentially
justified.
If it turned out that this was a necessary truth, one could then go on
to ask whether the same is true of the following, slightly stronger
proposition:
(b) Every belief is either non-inferentially justified, or justified on
the basis of some set of beliefs, each of which is non-inferentially
justified.
2. Later in this course, when we turn to the topic of the
justification of induction, we shall be considering the choice between
two competing conceptions of laws of nature. Confining oneself to
the case of non-probabilistic laws, one can characterize the two views
as follows. On the one hand, there is the reductionist view,
according to which laws of nature are simply certain cosmic
regularities. On the other hand, there is the metaphysically
robust, ‘governing’ conception of laws of nature, according to which
laws of nature are atomic states of affairs that logically determine
what cosmic regularities obtain.
Given that distinction between a reductionist view
of laws of nature, and a governing view, here are two possible theorems
that are crucially relevant to the epistemological question of whether
induction can be justified:
(a) If governing laws are logically impossible, then it can never be
probable, relative to one’s evidence, that any cosmic regularity
obtains.
(b) By contrast, if governing laws are logically possible, then it can
be probable, relative to one’s evidence, that certain cosmic
regularities obtain.
(4) The Development of a Systematic
Overview – a Synoptic View – of Reality as a Whole
What is involved in this fourth
activity? The basic goal here is to arrive at a picture of
reality as a whole that is both comprehensive and plausible.
Doing this may turn out to be considerably more difficult than one
would initially think. For it may turn out that some of the
things that one believes do not cohere very well with other things that
one believes. There may even be, or appear to be, outright
inconsistencies.
One Illustration: The Nature of
the Mind, and its Place in Reality
Consider physics. Its goal
is to provide a complete account of physical reality – including
both all of the fundamental particles and forces that make up the
physical world, and all of the laws that govern the those forces, and
the interactions of fundamental particles. But how does the mind
fit into this picture? Is it something more, something
non-physical? If it is, does it act upon the physical
world? Do particles in my brain behave differently because of the
causal impact of my mind upon those particles? If so, then
physics is not the complete story about the behavior of the things,
such as electrons, that make up the physical world? So isn't
there a serious tension, at the very least, between what physicists
tell us about the physical world, and beliefs that most of us have
about ourselves?
Another Illustration: Human
Freedom and Moral Responsibility, and the Determinism of Newtonian
Physics
In some cases, there may be more
than tension: beliefs in different areas may be, or at least
appear to be, inconsistent with one another. As an illustration,
suppose that one were living in the 19th century. On the one
hand, one would be confronted with a very remarkable scientific
achievement – Newtonian physics – that explained an extraordinary range
of phenomena, and that did so very, very precisely. Newtonian
physics is, however, completely deterministic: given the positions and
the velocities of every fundamental particle at some specific time, the
positions and the velocities of everything at any other time follows in
virtue of the laws of Newtonian physics. But on the other hand,
you might also have been strongly inclined to believe that you were
free in a significant way – so that you had the power, for example,
either to hold on to the pen that you're now holding for another ten
seconds, or to let it go instead. But if Newtonian physics were
true, could you be free in that way? Could you have the power
freely to choose to do either of those things?
There are various ways of
attempting to resolve this inconsistency, or apparent
inconsistency. One is to say that there is not really any
inconsistency, on the grounds that when the term "free" is correctly
analyzed, it turns out that freedom is perfectly compatible with
complete determinism. But another way is to give up one of the
beliefs in question: either one could conclude that Newtonian physics
is at best an approximation to the truth, and that the truth about the
physical world is that it is not completely deterministic – a
conclusion that would receive support if one moved from the 19th
century into the early part of 20th century, when quantum mechanics was
developed. Alternatively, one could conclude instead that freedom
is really an illusion that arises because one is not aware of the very
small events – namely, events in one's brain – that cause one's
behavior, and that in fact one is not really free.
1.2 Epistemology
Questions of justification lie at
the very center of epistemology, but, as we shall see, questions of
analysis are also very important.
1.2.1 Analysis
How does analysis comes into
epistemology? Essentially, in three main ways:
(1) There is the analysis of concepts that are themselves
epistemological concepts. The most obvious is the concept of
knowledge itself. But there are a number of other central
concepts, such as those of: (a) a belief's being justified; (b) a
belief's being inferred from another belief; (c) a belief's being
inferentially justified, or being a case of inferential
knowledge. Other important epistemological concepts include: (i)
the idea of a belief's being absolutely certain; (ii) the idea of
degrees of belief; (iii) the idea of logical probability; (iv) the idea
of epistemic probability.
(2) Secondly, there is the analysis of different types of statements,
such as:
(a) statements about physical objects; (b) statements about other
minds and their mental states – such as beliefs, desires, sensations,
experiences, etc.; and (c) statements about the past, and about the
future.
Why is analysis of such
statements important? The reason is that questions of analysis
interact with questions of justification. Thus, for example, what
account one gives of the justification of beliefs about physical
objects, or of beliefs about other minds, turns out to depend crucially
upon what the correct account is of the meaning of statements about
physical objects, and statements about other minds, respectively.
(3) Thirdly, when one attempts to analyze fundamental epistemological
concepts, or statements that express propositions that one may know, or
at least be justified in believing, other concepts may turn out to play
a role in the analysis. Thus, for example, counterfactual
statements – that is, statements that say that if one thing were the
case, something else would be the case – often enter into the
analysis. Such statements are used, for example, in some analyses
of epistemological concepts such as knowledge and inference, and in
some analyses of statements about physical objects, and of statements
about other minds. Moreover, it may turn out to be important, for
such analyses, what account is to be given of the truth conditions of
counterfactuals.
1.2.2 Justification
In answering skeptical challenges
to claims that one has knowledge, or at least justified beliefs, one
would like not only to show that one does have knowledge or justified
beliefs, but also to provide some positive account of how one has that
knowledge, or of how the claims in question are justified. So it
is natural to think here in terms of two tasks, connected with the
following questions:
(1) Can one have knowledge – or at least justified beliefs – that
various things are the case? For example, can one know that there
are physical objects, that there are other minds, that certain things
happened in the past, or that other things will happen in the future?
(2) If one can have such knowledge, or if one is justified in believing
certain things, what account is to be given of how it is that one has
that knowledge, or of what exactly the justification of the belief in
question is?
It may well be, however, that
though one can raise these two separate questions – the question of
whether one is justified, and the question of precisely what the
justification is, if one is in fact justified – that there is really
only a single task here, since it may well be that the only way of
answering the first question is by answering the second – that is, it
may be that the only way that one can show, for example, that one is
justified in believing that there are other minds is by defending some
specific, positive account of how beliefs about other minds can be
justified. Indeed, this is my own view. Some philosophers hold,
however, that the burden of proof is upon the skeptic in these areas,
and that unless the skeptic can offer some convincing reason for
accepting skepticism, then one is justified in rejecting it. If
this view of matters were correct, then one might well be able to
answer the first question without answering the second, since if one
could show that the skeptic's arguments were unsound, one would have
shown that our ordinary beliefs were justified, and showing that the
skeptic's arguments were unsound might not require any positive account
of the justification of the beliefs in question.
Showing that the skeptic’s
arguments are unsound could, in turn, be done in either of two
ways. First, one could examine individual arguments, and then
show that each argument had some flaw or another – either fallacious
reasoning, or an implausible premise. Secondly, however, one
might instead be able to develop some general argument that showed that
no skeptical argument could possibly be sound. As we shall see
when we turn to Michael Huemer’s discussion of skepticism, this is
precisely what G. E. Moore and Michael Huemer have attempted to do.
1.2.3 The Place of the Concept of
Knowledge in Epistemology
Epistemology is often referred to
as the theory of knowledge, so it is very natural indeed to think that
the concept of knowledge is essential to epistemology. When we
turn to Topic 2 – The Problem of Analyzing the Concept of Knowledge –
we shall see that a number of quite different views have been advanced
concerning how the concept of knowledge is to be analyzed, and it may
well be far from clear what the correct account. If the concept
of knowledge is essential to epistemology, this may seem troubling.
In addition, independently of the
question of what the correct analysis of the concept of knowledge is,
there are some puzzling questions that arise about the concept of
knowledge. One is this:
(1) How is knowledge related to epistemic probability? If S knows
that p, does this entail anything about the epistemic probability that
p has for S?
The reason that this question raises a puzzle is
this. On the one hand, if one hold that the proposition that S
knows that p entails that the epistemic probability that P has for S is
equal to 1, then it would seem that one has very little knowledge at
all. On the other hand, if one says that it need not be equal to
1, the question arises as to what the lower bound is on the epistemic
probability that p has for S if S knows that p, and then the only
non-arbitrary lower bound is 0.5. But isn’t that too low?
Can it be true that S knows that p if the probability that p has
relative to S’s evidence is only barely greater than 0.5?
Another, related puzzle is this:
(2) Suppose that S knows that p and that S also knows that Q.
Then isn’t it always possible in that situation for S to know that p
and q? But if S’s knowing that r places any lower bound at all on
the epistemic probability that r has for S, other than a lower bound of
1, then there will be cases where S knows that p and S knows that q,
but cannot thereby know that p and q, since the epistemic probability
of the conjunction p and q, may be sufficiently below the epistemic
probability of p and the epistemic probability of q that it falls below
the lower bound, unless the lower bound is equal to 1.
Both of these puzzles are very worrying, I think, if
one holds that the concept of knowledge is crucial for epistemology,
since these puzzles suggest that our concept of knowledge may very well
involve a hidden incoherence.
I do not think, however, that one
should be troubled by this, since I am not at all convinced that the
concept of knowledge is crucial for epistemology. Consider the
following question: “Why is knowledge better than justified
belief?” One answer is that if one knows something, then it
follows that the thing in question is true, whereas a belief may be
justified, but false. But then one can go on to ask, “Why is
knowledge better than justified, true belief?”
At one point, the answer that
most epistemologists would have given was that it wasn’t, since it was
widely thought that knowledge just was justified, true belief.
But as we shall see when we turn to Topic 2, there appear to be
excellent reasons for rejecting that analysis of knowledge. But
if one can have justified true belief that is not knowledge, the
question arises, as to whether knowledge is preferable to, or more
valuable than, justified true belief, and if so, how and why.
My own view is that the major
problems in epistemology can all be discussed in terms of the idea of
justified belief: the concept of knowledge is unnecessary.
1.2.4 Justified Belief,
Normativity, and the Threat of Moral Skepticism
Whether a belief is epistemically
justified is connected with whether one ought or not believe it.
What is the connection? A natural answer is this:
S ought to believe that p if and
only if S’s belief that p is epistemically justified.
But this overlooks the
possibility that there might be good reasons of a non-epistemological
sort for accepting or rejecting a belief. Pascal, in his famous
Wager Argument, attempted to show – unsuccessfully – that there was a
good prudential reason for believing in the existence of God even if it
one was epistemically justified in believing that the existence of God
was extremely unlikely. More generally, some beliefs that are
epistemically reasonable may be such that their acceptance has bad
consequences, while some beliefs that are epistemically unreasonable
may be such that their acceptance has good consequences.
The upshot is that one needs to
distinguish between an epistemic justification for a belief and a
non-epistemic justification for a belief. Then one can say,
If S’s belief that p is epistemically
justified, then, non-epistemic considerations aside, S ought to believe
that p, while if S’s belief that p is not epistemically justified,
then, non-epistemic considerations aside, S ought not to believe that
p,
Regardless of the details, however, it is
natural to connect the idea of a belief’s being justified or
unjustified with the idea of what one ought or ought not believe.
But if that’s right, then doesn’t epistemology rest upon the assumption
that there are objective moral truths, upon the supposition that moral
skepticism is not true?
If that’s right, isn’t that troubling? For
there are serious arguments – and arguments that many philosophers
believe are quite plausible – for the conclusion that moral skepticism
– often in the form of what is know as J. L. Mackie’s Error Theory – is
true.
Some philosophers have thought that one could use
this connection as an argument against moral skepticism, along the
following lines:
(1) Some of our beliefs are epistemically justified.
(2) If a belief is epistemically justified, then, other things being
equal, one should not reject that belief.
(3) If it is true that one should not reject certain beliefs, then
moral skepticism is false.
Conclusion:
(4) Moral skepticism is false.
My view is that this is a bad
argument against moral skepticism, and for two reasons.
The first is that it assumes that
skeptical arguments in epistemology can be refuted, and it is not at
all clear that the claim can be sustained.
The second point – and this
is the crucial one – is that epistemology does not need any normative
concepts. Consider the following claim:
Normative truths supervene –albeit
probably not in a logical or analytical sense of “supervenience” – upon
non-normative truths, in the sense that if state of affairs A differs
in axiological value from state of affairs B, then A and B must differ
with regard to non-normative properties or relations that they involve,
and, similarly, if action A differs in moral status from action B, then
A and B must differ with regard to non-normative properties or
relations that they involve.
Whether a belief is justified,
then, is something that must supervene upon non-normative states of
affairs. Consequently, epistemology can simply ignore
normativity, and focus upon the non-normative states of affairs that
underlie justification.
If those non-normative states of
affairs are complex, this will make epistemology somewhat messy.
But I don’t think that is the case, since it seems to me that the
relevant non-normative states of affairs are facts concerning epistemic
probability.
What is epistemic
probability? A full answer to that is tricky, but here’s a
starting point. First of all, one needs the idea of logical
probability, where this is a relation between propositions: the logical
probability of q given p is the probability that q is true given only
the information that p is true. Secondly, given the idea of
logical probability, one can say that if S’s belief that p is not
non-inferentially justified to any extent, then the epistemic
probability that p has for S is equal to the logical probability of p
relative to the conjunction of all of S’s non-inferentially justified
beliefs. Thirdly, that leaves one with the problem of defining
epistemic probability for beliefs that are non-inferentially
justified. One view is that the epistemic probability of any
non-inferentially justified belief is always equal to 1, but I’m not
convinced that that view is right.
The upshot is that it seems to me
that epistemology can in principle dispense with both the concept of
knowledge and the concept of justified belief, and focus instead simply
upon the epistemic probability that various beliefs are true.
2. The Content of this
Course
Given the above, I can now
describe very briefly what I shall and shall not be covering in this
course.
1. The course will be primarily concerned, first, with the
analysis of fundamental epistemological concepts – such as the concepts
of knowledge, and inference; secondly, with skeptical challenges to
claims to knowledge and justified belief in a variety of areas – such
as knowledge of the external world, knowledge of other minds, knowledge
of the past, and knowledge of general laws of nature; and thirdly, with
the different types of alternative accounts that can be offered of the
justification of one's beliefs in various areas.
2. There are, however, other sorts of knowledge claims that
people advance – concerning, for example: various religious questions,
such as that of the existence of God; questions in meta-ethics about
whether there are objective values; questions in ethics, about what
actions are right or wrong, and what things are good or bad; questions
in aesthetics, concerning the value of different works of art.
These are interesting and important questions. They are not,
however, questions that will be covered here. An investigation of
these and other claims to knowledge in controversial areas calls for
specialized discussions.
This is not to say, however, that
an understanding of the ways one can attempt to justify beliefs in
areas that – leaving aside for the moment skeptical challenges – are
relatively uncontroversial, is irrelevant to claims in more
controversial areas. On the contrary, it seems to me that
familiarity with the issues that arise in the more mundane areas of
perceptual knowledge, knowledge of other minds, knowledge of the past,
etc. can prove invaluable when one comes to examine knowledge claims in
other, much more controversial areas – such as religion, ethics, and
aesthetics.